background image

A

 

H

ISTORY

 

OF

 

T

RANSHUMANIST

 

T

HOUGHT

 

 

Nick

 

Bostrom

 

Faculty

 

of

 

Philosophy,

 

Oxford

 

University

 

www.nickbostrom.com

  

(2005)

 

[Originally

 

published

 

in

 

Journal

 

of

 

Evolution

 

and

 

Technology

  â€Â Â 

Vol.

 

14

  

Issue

 

1

 â€Â 

April

 

2005;

 

reprinted

 

(in

 

its

 

present

 

slightly

 

edited

 

form)

 

in

 

Academic

 

Writing

 

Across

 

the

 

Disciplines

,

 

eds.

 

Michael

 

Rectenwald

 

&

 

Lisa

 

Carl

 

(New

 

York:

 

Pearson

 

Longman,

 

2011)]

 

 

1.

 

Cultural

 

and

 

philosophical

 

antecedents

 

The

 

human

 

desire

 

to

 

acquire

 

new

 

capacities

 

is

 

as

 

ancient

 

as

 

our

 

species

 

itself.

 

We

 

have

 

always

 

sought

 

to

 

expand

 

the

 

boundaries

 

of

 

our

 

existence,

 

be

 

it

 

socially,

 

geographically,

 

or

 

mentally.

 

There

 

is

 

a

 

tendency

 

in

 

at

 

least

 

some

 

individuals

 

always

 

to

 

search

 

for

 

a

 

way

 

around

 

every

 

obstacle

 

and

 

limitation

 

to

 

human

 

life

 

and

 

happiness.

 

 

Ceremonial

 

burial

 

and

 

preserved

 

fragments

 

of

 

religious

 

writings

 

show

 

that

 

prehistoric

 

humans

 

were

 

disturbed

 

by

 

the

 

death

 

of

 

loved

 

ones.

 

Although

 

the

 

belief

 

in

 

a

 

hereafter

 

was

 

common,

 

this

 

did

 

not

 

preclude

 

efforts

 

to

 

extend

 

one’s

 

earthly

 

life.

 

In

 

the

 

Sumerian

 

Epic

 

of

 

Gilgamesh

 

(approx.

 

1700

 

B.C.),

 

a

 

king

 

sets

 

out

 

on

 

a

 

quest

 

for

 

immortality.

 

Gilgamesh

 

learns

 

that

 

there

 

exists

 

a

 

natural

 

means

 

–

 

an

 

herb

 

that

 

grows

 

at

 

the

 

bottom

 

of

 

the

 

sea.

1

 

He

 

successfully

 

retrieves

 

the

 

plant,

 

but

 

a

 

snake

 

steals

 

it

 

from

 

him

 

before

 

he

 

can

 

eat

 

it.

 

In

 

later

 

times,

 

explorers

 

sought

 

the

 

Fountain

 

of

 

Youth,

 

alchemists

 

labored

 

to

 

concoct

 

the

 

Elixir

 

of

 

Life,

 

and

 

various

 

schools

 

of

 

esoteric

 

Taoism

 

in

 

China

 

strove

 

for

 

physical

 

immortality

 

by

 

way

 

of

 

control

 

over

 

or

 

harmony

 

with

 

the

 

forces

 

of

 

nature.

 

The

 

boundary

 

between

 

mythos

 

and

 

science,

 

between

 

magic

 

and

 

technology,

 

was

 

blurry,

 

and

 

almost

 

all

 

conceivable

 

means

 

to

 

the

 

preservation

 

of

 

life

 

were

 

attempted

 

by

 

somebody

 

or

 

other.

 

Yet

 

while

 

explorers

 

made

 

many

 

interesting

 

discoveries

 

and

 

alchemists

 

invented

 

some

 

useful

 

things,

 

such

 

as

 

new

 

dyes

 

and

 

improvements

 

in

 

metallurgy,

 

the

 

goal

 

of

 

life

 

extension

 

proved

 

elusive.

 

  

The

 

quest

 

to

 

transcend

 

our

 

natural

 

confines

 

has

 

long

 

been

 

viewed

 

with

 

ambivalence

,

 

however.

 

Reining

 

it

 

in

 

is

 

the

 

concept

 

of

 

hubris

:

 

that

 

some

 

ambitions

 

are

 

off

â€

limits

 

and

 

will

 

backfire

 

if

 

pursued.

 

The

 

ancient

 

Greeks

 

exhibited

 

this

 

ambivalence

 

in

 

their

 

mythology.

 

Prometheus

 

stole

 

fire

 

from

 

Zeus

 

and

 

gave

 

it

 

to

 

humans,

 

thereby

 

permanently

 

improving

 

the

 

human

 

condition.

 

Yet

 

for

 

this

 

act

 

he

 

was

 

severely

 

punished

 

by

 

Zeus.

 

The

 

gods

 

are

 

repeatedly

 

                                                        

1

 

(Mitchell

 

2004).

 

 

1

background image

challenged,

 

quite

 

successfully,

 

by

 

Daedalus,

 

the

 

clever

 

engineer

 

and

 

artist,

 

who

 

uses

 

non

â€

magical

 

means

 

to

 

extend

 

human

 

capabilities.

 

In

 

the

 

end,

 

disaster

 

ensues

 

when

 

his

 

son

 

Icarus

 

ignores

 

paternal

 

warnings

 

and

 

flies

 

too

 

close

 

to

 

the

 

sun,

 

causing

 

the

 

wax

 

in

 

his

 

wings

 

to

 

melt.

 

 

Medieval

 

Christians

 

held

 

similarly

 

conflicted

 

views

 

about

 

the

 

pursuits

 

of

 

the

 

alchemists,

 

who

 

were

 

attempting

 

to

 

transmute

 

substances,

 

create

 

homunculi

 

in

 

test

 

tubes,

 

and

 

invent

 

a

 

panacea.

 

Some

 

scholastics,

 

following

 

the

 

anti

â€

experimentalist

 

teachings

 

of

 

Augustine,

 

believed

 

that

 

alchemy

 

was

 

an

 

ungodly

 

activity.

 

There

 

were

 

allegations

 

that

 

it

 

involved

 

the

 

invocation

 

of

 

daemonic

 

powers.

 

But

 

other

 

theologians,

 

such

 

as

 

Albertus

 

Magnus

 

and

 

Thomas

 

Aquinas,

 

defended

 

the

 

practice.

2

 

 

The

 

otherworldliness

 

and

 

stale

 

scholastic

 

philosophy

 

that

 

dominated

 

Europe

 

during

 

the

 

Middle

 

Ages

 

gave

 

way

 

to

 

a

 

renewed

 

intellectual

 

vigor

 

in

 

the

 

Renaissance.

 

The

 

human

 

being

 

and

 

the

 

natural

 

world

 

again

 

became

 

legitimate

 

objects

 

of

 

study.

 

Renaissance

 

humanism

 

encouraged

 

people

 

to

 

rely

 

on

 

their

 

own

 

observations

 

and

 

their

 

own

 

judgment

 

rather

 

than

 

to

 

defer

 

in

 

every

 

matter

 

to

 

religious

 

authorities.

 

Renaissance

 

humanism

 

also

 

created

 

the

 

ideal

 

of

 

the

 

well

â€

rounded

 

person,

 

one

 

who

 

is

 

highly

 

developed

 

scientifically,

 

morally,

 

culturally,

 

and

 

spiritually.

 

A

 

landmark

 

of

 

the

 

period

 

is

 

Giovanni

 

Pico

 

della

 

Mirandola’s

 

Oration

 

on

 

the

 

Dignity

 

of

 

Man

 

(1486),

 

which

 

proclaims

 

that

 

man

 

does

 

not

 

have

 

a

 

ready

â€

made

 

form

 

and

 

is

 

responsible

 

for

 

shaping

 

himself:

 

 

We

 

have

 

made

 

you

 

a

 

creature

 

neither

 

of

 

heaven

 

nor

 

of

 

earth,

 

neither

 

mortal

 

nor

 

immortal,

 

in

 

order

 

that

 

you

 

may,

 

as

 

the

 

free

 

and

 

proud

 

shaper

 

of

 

your

 

own

 

being,

 

fashion

 

yourself

 

in

 

the

 

form

 

you

 

may

 

prefer.

 

It

 

will

 

be

 

in

 

your

 

power

 

to

 

descend

 

to

 

the

 

lower,

 

brutish

 

forms

 

of

 

life;

 

you

 

will

 

be

 

able,

 

through

 

your

 

own

 

decision,

 

to

 

rise

 

again

 

to

 

the

 

superior

 

orders

 

whose

 

life

 

is

 

divine.

3

 

 

The

 

Age

 

of

 

Enlightenment

 

is

 

often

 

said

 

to

 

have

 

started

 

with

 

the

 

publication

 

of

 

Francis

 

Bacon’s

 

Novum

 

Organum

,

 

“the

 

new

 

toolâ€

 

(1620),

 

which

 

proposes

 

a

 

scientific

 

methodology

 

based

 

on

 

empirical

 

investigation

 

rather

 

than

 

a

â€

priori

 

reasoning.

 

4

 

Bacon

 

advocated

 

the

 

project

 

of

 

“effecting

 

all

 

things

 

possible,â€

 

by

 

which

 

he

 

meant

 

using

 

science

 

to

 

achieve

 

mastery

 

over

 

nature

 

in

 

order

 

to

 

improve

 

the

 

living

 

condition

 

of

 

human

 

beings.

 

The

 

heritage

 

from

 

the

 

Renaissance

 

combines

 

with

 

the

 

influence

 

of

 

Isaac

 

Newton,

 

Thomas

 

Hobbes,

 

John

 

Locke,

 

Immanuel

 

Kant,

 

the

 

Marquis

 

de

 

Condorcet,

 

and

 

others

 

to

 

form

 

the

 

basis

 

for

 

rational

 

                                                        

2

 

See

 

e.g.

 

(Newman

 

2004).

 

3

 

(Pico

 

della

 

Mirandola

 

1956).

  

4

 

(Bacon

 

1620).

 

 

2

background image

humanism,

 

which

 

emphasizes

 

empirical

 

science

 

and

 

critical

 

reason

 

–

 

rather

 

than

 

revelation

 

and

 

religious

 

authority

 

–

 

as

 

ways

 

of

 

learning

 

about

 

the

 

natural

 

world

 

and

 

our

 

place

 

within

 

it

 

and

 

of

 

providing

 

a

 

grounding

 

for

 

morality.

 

Transhumanism

 

has

 

roots

 

in

 

rational

 

humanism.

 

 

In

 

the

 

18

th

 

and

 

19

th

 

centuries

 

we

 

catch

 

glimpses

 

of

 

the

 

idea

 

that

 

humans

 

themselves

 

can

 

be

 

developed

 

through

 

the

 

application

 

of

 

science.

 

Condorcet

 

speculated

 

about

 

extending

 

human

 

life

 

span

 

by

 

means

 

of

 

medical

 

science:

 

 

Would

 

it

 

be

 

absurd

 

now

 

to

 

suppose

 

that

 

the

 

improvement

 

of

 

the

 

human

 

race

 

should

 

be

 

regarded

 

as

 

capable

 

of

 

unlimited

 

progress?

 

That

 

a

 

time

 

will

 

come

 

when

 

death

 

would

 

result

 

only

 

from

 

extraordinary

 

accidents

 

or

 

the

 

more

 

and

 

more

 

gradual

 

wearing

 

out

 

of

 

vitality,

 

and

 

that,

 

finally,

 

the

 

duration

 

of

 

the

 

average

 

interval

 

between

 

birth

 

and

 

wearing

 

out

 

has

 

itself

 

no

 

specific

 

limit

 

whatsoever?

 

No

 

doubt

 

man

 

will

 

not

 

become

 

immortal,

 

but

 

cannot

 

the

 

span

 

constantly

 

increase

 

between

 

the

 

moment

 

he

 

begins

 

to

 

live

 

and

 

the

 

time

 

when

 

naturally,

 

without

 

illness

 

or

 

accident,

 

he

 

finds

 

life

 

a

 

burden?

5

 

 

Benjamin

 

Franklin

 

longed

 

wistfully

 

for

 

suspended

 

animation,

 

foreshadowing

 

the

 

cryonics

 

movement:

 

 

I

 

wish

 

it

 

were

 

possible...

 

to

 

invent

 

a

 

method

 

of

 

embalming

 

drowned

 

persons,

 

in

 

such

 

a

 

manner

 

that

 

they

 

might

 

be

 

recalled

 

to

 

life

 

at

 

any

 

period,

 

however

 

distant;

 

for

 

having

 

a

 

very

 

ardent

 

desire

 

to

 

see

 

and

 

observe

 

the

 

state

 

of

 

America

 

a

 

hundred

 

years

 

hence,

 

I

 

should

 

prefer

 

to

 

an

 

ordinary

 

death,

 

being

 

immersed

 

with

 

a

 

few

 

friends

 

in

 

a

 

cask

 

of

 

Madeira,

 

until

 

that

 

time,

 

then

 

to

 

be

 

recalled

 

to

 

life

 

by

 

the

 

solar

 

warmth

 

of

 

my

 

dear

 

country!

 

But...

 

in

 

all

 

probability,

 

we

 

live

 

in

 

a

 

century

 

too

 

little

 

advanced,

 

and

 

too

 

near

 

the

 

infancy

 

of

 

science,

 

to

 

see

 

such

 

an

 

art

 

brought

 

in

 

our

 

time

 

to

 

its

 

perfection.

6

 

 

After

 

the

 

publication

 

of

 

Darwin’s

 

Origin

 

of

 

Species

 

(1859),

 

it

 

became

 

increasingly

 

plausible

 

to

 

view

 

the

 

current

 

version

 

of

 

humanity

 

not

 

as

 

the

 

endpoint

 

of

 

evolution

 

but

 

rather

 

as

 

an

 

early

 

phase.

7

 

The

 

rise

 

of

 

scientific

 

physicalism

 

might

 

also

 

have

 

contributed

 

to

 

the

 

belief

 

that

 

technology

 

might

 

well

 

improve

 

the

 

human

 

organism.

 

For

 

example,

 

a

 

simple

 

kind

 

of

 

materialist

 

view

 

was

 

boldly

 

proposed

 

in

 

1750

 

by

 

the

 

French

 

physician

 

and

 

materialist

 

philosopher

 

Julien

 

Offray

 

de

 

La

 

Mettrie

 

in

 

L’Homme

 

Machine

,

 

in

 

which

 

he

 

argued

 

that

 

“man

 

                                                        

5

 

(Condorcet

 

1979).

 

6

 

(Franklin

 

et

 

al.

 

1956),

 

pp.

 

27

â€

29.

 

7

 

(Darwin

 

2003).

 

 

3

background image

is

 

but

 

an

 

animal,

 

or

 

a

 

collection

 

of

 

springs

 

which

 

wind

 

each

 

other

 

up.â€

8

 

If

 

human

 

beings

 

are

 

constituted

 

of

 

matter

 

obeying

 

s

 

the

 

same

 

laws

 

of

 

physics

 

that

 

operate

 

outside

 

us,

 

then

 

it

 

should

 

in

 

principle

 

be

 

possible

 

to

 

learn

 

to

 

manipulate

 

human

 

nature

 

in

 

the

 

same

 

way

 

that

 

we

 

manipulate

 

external

 

objects.

 

 

The

 

Enlightenment

 

is

 

said

 

to

 

have

 

expired

 

as

 

the

 

victim

 

of

 

its

 

own

 

excesses.

 

It

 

gave

 

way

 

to

 

Romanticism

 

and

 

to

 

latter

â€

day

 

reactions

 

against

 

the

 

rule

 

of

 

instrumental

 

reason

 

and

 

the

 

attempt

 

to

 

rationally

 

control

 

nature,

 

such

 

as

 

can

 

be

 

found

 

in

 

some

 

postmodernist

 

writings,

 

the

 

New

 

Age

 

movement,

 

deep

 

environmentalism,

 

and

 

parts

 

of

 

the

 

anti

â€

globalization

 

movement.

 

However,

 

the

 

Enlightenment’s

 

legacy,

 

including

 

a

 

belief

 

in

 

the

 

power

 

of

 

human

 

rationality

 

and

 

science,

 

is

 

still

 

an

 

important

 

shaper

 

of

 

modern

 

culture.

 

In

 

his

 

famous

 

1784

 

essay

 

“What

 

Is

 

Enlightenment?â€,

 

Kant

 

summed

 

it

 

up

 

as

 

follows:

 

 

Enlightenment

 

is

 

man’s

 

leaving

 

his

 

self

â€

caused

 

immaturity.

 

Immaturity

 

is

 

the

 

incapacity

 

to

 

use

 

one’s

 

own

 

understanding

 

without

 

the

 

guidance

 

of

 

another.

 

Such

 

immaturity

 

is

 

self

â€

caused

 

if

 

its

 

cause

 

is

 

not

 

lack

 

of

 

intelligence,

 

but

 

by

 

lack

 

of

 

determination

 

and

 

courage

 

to

 

use

 

one’s

 

intelligence

 

without

 

being

 

guided

 

by

 

another.

 

The

 

motto

 

of

 

enlightenment

 

is

 

therefore:

 

Sapere

 

aude!

 

Have

 

courage

 

to

 

use

 

your

 

own

 

intelligence!

9

 

 

It

 

might

 

be

 

thought

 

that

 

a

 

major

 

inspiration

 

for

 

transhumanism

 

was

 

Friedrich

 

Nietzsche,

 

famous

 

for

 

his

 

doctrine

 

of

 

der

 

Ãœbermensch

:

  

 

I

 

teach

 

you

 

the

 

overman.

 

Man

 

is

 

something

 

that

 

shall

 

be

 

overcome.

 

What

 

have

 

you

 

done

 

to

 

overcome

 

him?

 

All

 

beings

 

so

 

far

 

have

 

created

 

something

 

beyond

 

themselves;

 

and

 

do

 

you

 

want

 

to

 

be

 

the

 

ebb

 

of

 

this

 

great

 

flood

 

and

 

even

 

go

 

back

 

to

 

the

 

beasts

 

rather

 

than

 

overcome

 

man?

10

 

 

What

 

Nietzsche

 

had

 

in

 

mind,

 

however,

 

was

 

not

 

technological

 

transformation

 

but

 

a

 

kind

 

of

 

soaring

 

personal

 

growth

 

and

 

cultural

 

refinement

 

in

 

exceptional

 

individuals

 

(who

 

he

 

thought

 

would

 

have

 

to

 

overcome

 

the

 

life

â€

sapping

 

“slave

â€

moralityâ€

 

of

 

Christianity).

 

Despite

 

some

 

surface

â€

level

 

similarities

 

with

 

the

 

Nietzschean

 

vision,

 

transhumanism

 

–

 

with

 

its

 

Enlightenment

 

roots,

 

its

 

emphasis

 

on

 

individual

 

liberties,

 

and

 

its

 

humanistic

 

concern

 

for

 

the

 

welfare

 

of

 

all

 

humans

 

(and

 

other

 

sentient

 

beings)

 

–

 

probably

 

has

 

as

 

much

 

or

 

more

 

in

 

                                                        

8

 

(La

 

Mettrie

 

1996).

 

9

 

(Kant

 

1986).

 

10

 

(Nietzsche

 

1908).

 

 

4

background image

common

 

with

 

Nietzsche’s

 

contemporary

 

the

 

English

 

liberal

 

thinker

 

and

 

utilitarian

 

John

 

Stuart

 

Mill.

 

 

2.

 

Speculation,

 

science

 

fiction,

 

and

 

twentieth

â€

century

 

totalitarianism

 

In

 

1923,

 

the

 

noted

 

British

 

biochemist

 

J.

 

B.

 

S.

 

Haldane

 

published

 

the

 

essay

 

Daedalus;

 

or,

 

Science

 

and

 

the

 

Future

,

 

in

 

which

 

he

 

argued

 

that

 

great

 

benefits

 

would

 

come

 

from

 

controlling

 

our

 

own

 

genetics

 

and

 

from

 

science

 

in

 

general.

 

He

 

predicted

 

a

 

wealthier

 

society,

 

with

 

abundant

 

clean

 

energy,

 

where

 

genetics

 

would

 

be

 

employed

 

to

 

make

 

people

 

taller,

 

healthier,

 

and

 

smarter

 

and

 

where

 

ectogenesis

 

(gestating

 

fetuses

 

in

 

artificial

 

wombs)

 

would

 

be

 

commonplace.

 

He

 

also

 

commented

 

on

 

what

 

has

 

in

 

recent

 

years

 

become

 

known

 

as

 

the

 

“yuck

 

factorâ€:

 

 

The

 

chemical

 

or

 

physical

 

inventor

 

is

 

always

 

a

 

Prometheus.

 

There

 

is

 

no

 

great

 

invention,

 

from

 

fire

 

to

 

flying,

 

which

 

has

 

not

 

been

 

hailed

 

as

 

an

 

insult

 

to

 

some

 

god.

 

But

 

if

 

every

 

physical

 

and

 

chemical

 

invention

 

is

 

a

 

blasphemy,

 

every

 

biological

 

invention

 

is

 

a

 

perversion.

 

There

 

is

 

hardly

 

one

 

which,

 

on

 

first

 

being

 

brought

 

to

 

the

 

notice

 

of

 

an

 

observer

 

from

 

any

 

nation

 

which

 

has

 

not

 

previously

 

heard

 

of

 

their

 

existence,

 

would

 

not

 

appear

 

to

 

him

 

as

 

indecent

 

and

 

unnatural.

11

 

 

Haldane’s

 

essay

 

became

 

a

 

bestseller

 

and

 

set

 

off

 

a

 

chain

 

of

 

future

â€

oriented

 

discussions,

 

including

 

The

 

World,

 

the

 

Flesh

 

and

 

the

 

Devil

,

 

by

 

J.

 

D.

 

Bernal

 

(1929)

12

,

 

which

 

speculated

 

about

 

space

 

colonization

 

and

 

bionic

 

implants

 

as

 

well

 

as

 

mental

 

improvements

 

arising

 

from

 

advanced

 

social

 

science

 

and

 

psychology;

 

the

 

works

 

of

 

Olaf

 

Stapledon,

 

a

 

philosopher

 

and

 

science

 

fiction

 

author;

 

and

 

the

 

essay

 

“Icarus:

 

the

 

Future

 

of

 

Scienceâ€

 

(1924)

 

by

 

Bertrand

 

Russell.

13

 

Russell

 

took

 

a

 

more

 

pessimistic

 

view,

 

arguing

 

that

 

without

 

more

 

kindliness

 

in

 

the

 

world,

 

technological

 

power

 

would

 

mainly

 

serve

 

to

 

increase

 

our

 

ability

 

to

 

harm

 

one

 

another.

 

Science

 

fiction

 

authors

 

such

 

as

 

H.

 

G.

 

Wells

 

and

 

Stapledon

 

got

 

many

 

people

 

thinking

 

about

 

the

 

future

 

evolution

 

of

 

the

 

human

 

race.

 

 

Aldous

 

Huxley’s

 

Brave

 

New

 

World

,

 

published

 

in

 

1932,

 

has

 

had

 

an

 

enduring

 

impact

 

on

 

debates

 

about

 

human

 

technological

 

transformation

14

 

matched

 

by

 

few

 

other

 

works

 

of

 

fiction

 

(possibly

 

excepting

 

Mary

 

Shelley’s

 

Frankenstein

15

).

 

Huxley

 

describes

 

a

 

dystopia

 

where

 

psychological

 

conditioning,

 

promiscuous

 

sexuality,

 

biotechnology,

 

and

 

the

 

opiate

 

drug

 

“somaâ€

 

keep

 

the

 

population

 

placid

 

in

 

a

 

static,

 

conformist

 

caste

 

society

 

governed

 

by

 

ten

 

                                                        

11

 

(Haldane

 

1924).

 

12

 

(Bernal

 

1929[1969]).

 

13

 

(Russell

 

1924)

 

14

 

(Huxley

 

1932).

 

15

 

(Shelley

 

1818).

 

 

5

background image

world

 

controllers.

 

Children

 

are

 

manufactured

 

in

 

fertility

 

clinics

 

and

 

artificially

 

gestated.

 

The

 

lower

 

castes

 

are

 

chemically

 

stunted

 

or

 

deprived

 

of

 

oxygen

 

during

 

their

 

maturation

 

process

,

 

in

 

order

 

to

 

limit

 

their

 

physical

 

and

 

intellectual

 

development.

 

From

 

birth,

 

members

 

of

 

every

 

caste

 

are

 

indoctrinated

 

during

 

their

 

sleep,

 

by

 

recorded

 

voices

 

repeating

 

the

 

slogans

 

of

 

the

 

official

 

“Fordistâ€

 

religion,

 

and

 

conditioned

 

to

 

believe

 

that

 

their

 

own

 

caste

 

is

 

the

 

best

 

one

 

to

 

belong

 

to.

 

The

 

society

 

depicted

 

in

 

Brave

 

New

 

World

 

is

 

often

 

likened

 

to

 

another

 

influential

 

20

th

 

century

 

dystopia,

 

that

 

of

 

George

 

Orwell’s

 

Nineteen

 

Eighty

â€

Four

.

16

 

Nineteen

 

Eighty

â€

Four

 

features

 

a

 

more

 

overt

 

form

 

of

 

oppression,

 

including

 

ubiquitous

 

surveillance

 

by

 

“Big

 

Brotherâ€

 

and

 

brutal

 

police

 

coercion.

 

Huxley’s

 

world

 

controllers,

 

by

 

contrast,

 

rely

 

on

 

less

 

blatant

 

means

 

(bio

â€

engineered

 

predestination,

 

psychological

 

conditioning,

 

soma)

 

to

 

prevent

 

people

 

from

 

wanting

 

to

 

think

 

for

 

themselves.

 

Herd

 

mentality

 

and

 

promiscuity

 

are

 

promoted,

 

while

 

high

 

art,

 

individuality,

 

knowledge

 

of

 

history,

 

and

 

romantic

 

love

 

are

 

discouraged.

 

It

 

should

 

be

 

noted

 

that

 

in

 

neither

 

Nineteen

 

Eighty

â€

Four

 

nor

 

Brave

 

New

 

World

 

is

 

technology

 

employed

 

to

 

increase

 

human

 

capacities;

 

rather,

 

society

 

is

 

set

 

up

 

to

 

repress

 

the

 

full

 

development

 

of

 

humanity.

 

Both

 

dystopias

 

curtail

 

scientific

 

and

 

technological

 

exploration

 

for

 

fear

 

of

 

upsetting

 

the

 

social

 

equilibrium.

 

Nevertheless,

 

Brave

 

New

 

World

 

in

 

particular

 

has

 

become

 

an

 

emblem

 

of

 

the

 

dehumanizing

 

potential

 

of

 

the

 

use

 

of

 

technology

 

to

 

promote

 

social

 

conformism

 

and

 

shallow

 

contentment.

 

 

In

 

the

 

early

 

decades

 

of

 

the

 

20

th

 

century,

 

not

 

only

 

racists

 

and

 

right

â€

wing

 

ideologues

 

but

 

also

 

a

 

number

 

of

 

left

â€

leaning

 

social

 

progressives

 

became

 

concerned

 

about

 

the

 

effects

 

of

 

medicine

 

and

 

social

 

safety

 

nets

 

on

 

the

 

quality

 

of

 

the

 

human

 

gene

 

pool.

 

They

 

believed

 

that

 

modern

 

society

 

enabled

 

many

 

“unfitâ€

 

individuals

 

to

 

survive—individuals

 

who

 

would

 

in

 

earlier

 

ages

 

have

 

perished—and

 

they

 

worried

 

that

 

this

 

would

 

lead

 

to

 

a

 

deterioration

 

of

 

the

 

human

 

stock.

 

As

 

a

 

result,

 

many

 

countries

 

(including

 

the

 

USA,

 

Canada,

 

Australia,

 

Sweden,

 

Denmark,

 

Finland,

 

and

 

Switzerland)

 

implemented

 

state

â€

sponsored

 

eugenics

 

programs,

 

which

 

infringed

 

in

 

various

 

degree

 

on

 

individual

 

rights.

 

In

 

the

 

United

 

States,

 

between

 

1907

 

and

 

1963

 

some

 

64,000

 

individuals

 

were

 

forcibly

 

sterilized

 

under

 

eugenics

 

laws.

 

The

 

principal

 

victims

 

of

 

the

 

American

 

program

 

were

 

the

 

mentally

 

disabled,

 

but

 

the

 

deaf,

 

the

 

blind,

 

the

 

epileptic,

 

the

 

physically

 

deformed,

 

orphans,

 

and

 

the

 

homeless

 

were

 

also

 

sometimes

 

targeted.

  

But

 

even

 

such

 

widespread

 

compulsory

 

sterilization

 

pales

 

in

 

comparison

 

with

 

the

 

German

 

eugenics

 

program,

 

which

 

resulted

 

in

 

the

 

systematic

 

murder

 

of

 

millions

 

of

 

people

 

regarded

 

as

 

“inferiorâ€

 

by

 

the

 

Nazis.

 

 

The

 

holocaust

 

left

 

a

 

scar

 

on

 

the

 

human

 

psyche.

 

Determined

 

not

 

to

 

let

 

history

 

repeat

 

itself,

 

most

 

people

 

developed

 

an

 

instinctive

 

revulsion

 

to

 

all

 

ideas

 

appearing

 

to

 

have

 

any

 

kind

 

of

 

association

 

with

 

Nazi

 

ideology.

 

(And

 

yet,

 

it

 

must

 

be

 

remembered,

 

history

 

did

 

repeat

 

itself

,

 

                                                        

16

 

(Orwell

 

1949).

 

 

6

background image

e.g.

 

in

 

the

 

Rwandan

 

genocide

 

of

 

1994,

 

in

 

which

 

the

 

world

 

did

 

nothing

 

but

 

wring

 

its

 

hands

 

as

 

800,000

 

Africans

 

were

 

slaughtered.)

 

In

 

particular,

 

the

 

eugenics

 

movement

 

as

 

a

 

whole,

 

in

 

all

 

its

 

forms,

 

became

 

discredited

 

because

 

of

 

the

 

terrible

 

crimes

 

that

 

had

 

been

 

committed

 

in

 

its

 

name,

 

although

 

some

 

of

 

the

 

milder

 

eugenics

 

programs

 

continued

 

for

 

many

 

years

 

before

 

they

 

were

 

finally

 

scrapped.

 

These

 

programs

 

are

 

all

 

now

 

almost

 

universally

 

condemned.

 

The

 

goal

 

of

 

creating

 

a

 

new

 

and

 

better

 

world

 

through

 

a

 

centrally

 

imposed

 

vision

 

became

 

passé.

 

The

 

Stalinist

 

tyranny,

 

too,

 

underscored

 

the

 

dangers

 

of

 

totalitarian

 

utopianism.

 

 

In

 

the

 

postwar

 

era,

 

many

 

optimistic

 

futurists

 

who

 

had

 

become

 

suspicious

 

of

 

collectively

 

orchestrated

 

social

 

change

 

found

 

a

 

new

 

home

 

for

 

their

 

hopes

 

in

 

scientific

 

and

 

technological

 

progress.

 

Space

 

travel,

 

medicine,

 

and

 

computers

 

seemed

 

to

 

offer

 

a

 

path

 

to

 

a

 

better

 

world.

 

The

 

shift

 

of

 

attention

 

also

 

reflected

 

the

 

breathtaking

 

pace

 

of

 

development

 

in

 

these

 

fields.

 

Science

 

had

 

begun

 

to

 

catch

 

up

 

with

 

speculation.

  

Transhumanist

 

themes

 

during

 

this

 

period

 

were

 

discussed

 

and

 

analyzed

 

chiefly

 

in

 

the

 

science

 

fiction

 

literature.

 

Authors

 

such

 

as

 

Arthur

 

C.

 

Clarke,

 

Isaac

 

Asimov,

 

Robert

 

Heinlein,

 

and

 

Stanislaw

 

Lem

 

explored

 

how

 

technological

 

development

 

could

 

come

 

to

 

profoundly

 

alter

 

the

 

human

 

condition.

 

 

The

 

word

 

“transhumanismâ€

 

appears

 

to

 

have

 

been

 

first

 

used

 

by

 

Aldous

 

Huxley’s

 

brother,

 

Julian

 

Huxley,

 

a

 

distinguished

 

biologist

 

(who

 

was

 

also

 

the

 

first

 

director

â€

general

 

of

 

UNESCO

 

and

 

a

 

founder

 

of

 

the

 

World

 

Wildlife

 

Fund).

 

In

 

Religion

 

Without

 

Revelation

 

(1927),

 

he

 

wrote:

 

 

The

 

human

 

species

 

can,

 

if

 

it

 

wishes,

 

transcend

 

itself

 

–

 

not

 

just

 

sporadically,

 

an

 

individual

 

here

 

in

 

one

 

way,

 

an

 

individual

 

there

 

in

 

another

 

way

 

–

 

but

 

in

 

its

 

entirety,

 

as

 

humanity.

 

We

 

need

 

a

 

name

 

for

 

this

 

new

 

belief.

 

Perhaps

 

transhumanism

 

will

 

serve:

 

man

 

remaining

 

man,

 

but

 

transcending

 

himself,

 

by

 

realizing

 

new

 

possibilities

 

of

 

and

 

for

 

his

 

human

 

nature.

17

 

 

 

3.

 

Technological

 

genies:

 

AI,

 

the

 

singularity,

 

nanotech,

 

and

 

uploading

 

Human

â€

like

 

automata

 

have

 

always

 

fascinated

 

the

 

human

 

imagination.

 

Mechanical

 

engineers

 

since

 

the

 

early

 

Greeks

 

have

 

constructed

 

clever

 

self

â€

moving

 

devices.

 

 

In

 

Judaic

 

mysticism,

 

a

 

“golemâ€

 

refers

 

to

 

an

 

animated

 

being

 

crafted

 

from

 

inanimate

 

material.

 

In

 

the

 

early

 

golem

 

stories,

 

a

 

golem

 

could

 

be

 

created

 

by

 

a

 

holy

 

person

 

who

 

was

 

able

 

to

 

share

 

some

 

of

 

God’s

 

wisdom

 

and

 

power

 

(although

 

the

 

golem,

 

not

 

being

 

able

 

to

 

speak,

 

was

 

never

 

more

 

than

 

a

 

shadow

 

of

 

God’s

 

creations).

 

Having

 

a

 

golem

 

servant

 

was

 

the

 

ultimate

 

symbol

 

of

 

                                                        

17

 

(Huxley

 

1927),

 

quoted

 

from

 

(Hughes

 

2004).

 

 

7

background image

wisdom

 

and

 

holiness.

 

In

 

the

 

later

 

stories,

 

which

 

were

 

influenced

 

by

 

the

 

more

 

Islamic

 

concern

 

about

 

humanity

’s

 

getting

 

too

 

close

 

to

 

God,

 

the

 

golem

 

became

 

a

 

creation

 

of

 

overreaching

 

mystics

 

who

 

were

 

inevitably

 

punished

 

for

 

their

 

blasphemy.

 

The

 

story

 

of

 

the

 

Sorcerer’s

 

Apprentice

 

is

 

a

 

variation

 

of

 

this

 

theme:

 

The

 

apprentice

 

animates

 

a

 

broomstick

 

to

 

fetch

 

water

 

but

 

is

 

unable

 

to

 

make

 

the

 

broom

 

stop

 

–

 

like

 

Frankenstein

,

 

it

 

is,

 

a

 

story

 

of

 

technology

 

out

 

of

 

control.

 

The

 

word

 

“robotâ€

 

was

 

coined

 

by

 

the

 

Czech

 

writer

 

Karel

 Č

apek,

 

in

 

his

 

dark

 

play

 

R.U.R.

 

(1921),

 

in

 

which

 

a

 

robot

 

labor

 

force

 

destroys

 

its

 

human

 

creators.

18

 

With

 

the

 

invention

 

of

 

the

 

electronic

 

computer,

 

the

 

idea

 

of

 

human

â€

like

 

automata

 

graduated

 

from

 

the

 

kindergarten

 

of

 

mythology

 

to

 

the

 

school

 

of

 

science

 

fiction

 

(Asimov,

 

Lem,

 

Clarke)

 

and

 

eventually

 

to

 

the

 

college

 

of

 

technological

 

prediction.

 

 

Could

 

continued

 

progress

 

in

 

artificial

 

intelligence

 

lead

 

to

 

the

 

creation

 

of

 

machines

 

that

 

think

 

in

 

the

 

same

 

general

 

way

 

as

 

human

 

beings?

 

Alan

 

Turing

 

gave

 

an

 

operational

 

definition

 

to

 

this

 

question

 

in

 

his

 

classic

 

“Computing

 

Machinery

 

and

 

Intelligenceâ€

 

(1950)

 

and

 

predicted

 

that

 

computers

 

would

 

eventually

 

pass

 

what

 

came

 

to

 

be

 

known

 

as

 

the

 

Turing

 

Test.

 

In

 

the

 

Turing

 

Test,

 

a

 

human

 

experimenter

 

interviews

 

a

 

computer

 

and

 

another

 

human

 

via

 

a

 

text

 

interface

;

 

the

 

computer

 

succeeds

 

if

 

the

 

interviewer

 

cannot

 

reliably

 

distinguish

 

it

 

from

 

the

 

human.)

19

 

Much

 

ink

 

has

 

been

 

spilt

 

in

 

debates

 

on

 

whether

 

this

 

test

 

furnishes

 

a

 

necessary

 

and

 

sufficient

 

condition

 

for

 

a

 

computer

 

being

 

able

 

to

 

think,

 

but

 

what

 

matters

 

more

 

from

 

a

 

practical

 

perspective

 

is

 

whether

 

and,

 

if

 

so,

 

when

 

computers

 

will

 

be

 

able

 

to

 

match

 

human

 

performance

 

in

 

tasks

 

involving

 

general

 

reasoning

 

ability.

 

With

 

the

 

benefit

 

of

 

hindsight,

 

we

 

can

 

say

 

that

 

many

 

of

 

the

 

early

 

AI

 

researchers

 

turned

 

out

 

to

 

be

 

overoptimistic

 

about

 

the

 

timescale

 

for

 

this

 

hypothetical

 

development.

 

Of

 

course,

 

the

 

fact

 

that

 

we

 

have

 

not

 

yet

 

reached

 

human

â€

level

 

artificial

 

intelligence

 

does

 

not

 

mean

 

that

 

we

 

never

 

will,

 

and

 

a

 

number

 

of

 

people,

 

e.g.

 

Marvin

 

Minsky,

 

Hans

 

Moravec,

 

Ray

 

Kurzweil,

 

and

 

Nick

 

Bostrom

 

have

 

put

 

forward

 

reasons

 

for

 

taking

 

seriously

 

the

 

possibility

 

that

 

this

 

could

 

happen

 

within

 

the

 

first

 

half

 

of

 

this

 

century.

20

 

 

In

 

a

 

1958

 

tribute,

 

the

 

Polish

 

mathematician

 

Stanislaw

 

Ulam,

 

referring

 

to

 

a

 

meeting

 

with

 

his

 

late

 

colleague

 

John

 

von

 

Neumann,

 

wrote:

 

 

One

 

conversation

 

centered

 

on

 

the

 

ever

 

accelerating

 

progress

 

of

 

technology

 

and

 

changes

 

in

 

the

 

mode

 

of

 

human

 

life,

 

which

 

gives

 

the

 

appearance

 

of

 

approaching

 

some

 

essential

 

singularity

 

in

 

the

 

history

 

of

 

the

 

race

 

beyond

 

which

 

human

 

affairs,

 

as

 

we

 

know

 

them,

 

could

 

not

 

continue.

21

 

                                                        

18

 

(Capek

 

2004).

 

19

 

(Turing

 

1950).

 

20

 

(Minsky

 

1994;

 

Moravec

 

1999;

 

Bostrom

 

1998,

 

2002;

 

Kurzweil

 

1999).

 

21

 

(Ulam

 

1958).

 

 

8

background image

 

The

 

rapidity

 

of

 

technological

 

change

 

in

 

recent

 

times

 

leads

 

naturally

 

to

 

the

 

idea

 

that

 

continued

 

technological

 

innovation

 

will

 

have

 

a

 

profound

 

effect

 

on

 

humanity

 

in

 

the

 

decades

 

ahead.

 

This

 

prediction

 

is

 

strengthened

 

if

 

one

 

believes

 

that

 

some

 

of

 

those

 

variables

 

that

 

currently

 

exhibit

 

exponential

 

growth

 

will

 

continue

 

to

 

do

 

so

 

and

 

that

 

they

 

will

 

be

 

among

 

the

 

main

 

drivers

 

of

 

change.

 

Gordon

 

E.

 

Moore,

 

co

â€

founder

 

of

 

Intel,

 

noticed

 

in

 

1965

 

that

 

the

 

number

 

of

 

transistors

 

on

 

a

 

chip

 

exhibited

 

exponential

 

growth.

 

This

 

led

 

to

 

the

 

formulation

 

of

 

“Moore’s

 

lawâ€,

 

which

 

states

 

(roughly)

 

that

 

computing

 

power

 

doubles

 

every

 

eighteen

 

months

 

to

 

two

 

years.

22

 

More

 

recently,

 

Kurzweil

 

has

 

documented

 

similar

 

exponential

 

growth

 

rates

 

in

 

a

 

number

 

of

 

other

 

technologies.

 

It

 

is

 

interesting

 

to

 

note

 

that

 

the

 

world

 

economy,

 

a

 

general

 

index

 

of

 

humanity’s

 

productive

 

capacity,

 

has

 

doubled

 

about

 

every

 

fifteen

 

years

 

in

 

modern

 

times.

 

 

The

 

singularity

 

hypothesis,

 

to

 

which

 

von

 

Neumann

 

seemingly

 

alludes

 

in

 

the

 

quoted

 

passage

 

above,

 

holds

 

that

 

these

 

changes

 

will

 

lead

 

to

 

some

 

kind

 

of

 

discontinuity.

 

But

 

nowadays

 

it

 

often

 

refers

 

to

 

a

 

more

 

specific

 

prediction

:

 

namely

,

 

that

 

the

 

creation

 

of

 

self

â€

improving

 

artificial

 

intelligence

 

will

 

at

 

some

 

point

 

result

 

in

 

radical

 

changes

 

within

 

a

 

very

 

short

 

time

 

span.

 

This

 

hypothesis

 

was

 

first

 

clearly

 

stated

 

in

 

1965

 

by

 

the

 

statistician

 

I.

 

J.

 

Good:

 

 

Let

 

an

 

ultraintelligent

 

machine

 

be

 

defined

 

as

 

a

 

machine

 

that

 

can

 

far

 

surpass

 

all

 

the

 

intellectual

 

activities

 

of

 

any

 

man

 

however

 

clever.

 

Since

 

the

 

design

 

of

 

machines

 

is

 

one

 

of

 

these

 

intellectual

 

activities,

 

an

 

ultraintelligent

 

machine

 

could

 

design

 

even

 

better

 

machines;

 

there

 

would

 

then

 

unquestionably

 

be

 

an

 

‘intelligence

 

explosion,’

 

and

 

the

 

intelligence

 

of

 

man

 

would

 

be

 

left

 

far

 

behind.

 

Thus

 

the

 

first

 

ultraintelligent

 

machine

 

is

 

the

 

last

 

invention

 

that

 

man

 

need

 

ever

 

make.

23

 

 

Vernor

 

Vinge

 

discussed

 

this

 

idea

 

in

 

a

 

little

 

more

 

detail

 

in

 

his

 

influential

 

1993

â€

paper

 

“Technological

 

Singularityâ€,

 

in

 

which

 

he

 

predicted:

  

 

Within

 

thirty

 

years,

 

we

 

will

 

have

 

the

 

technological

 

means

 

to

 

create

 

superhuman

 

intelligence.

 

Shortly

 

after,

 

the

 

human

 

era

 

will

 

be

 

ended.

24

 

 

Transhumanists

 

today

 

hold

 

diverging

 

views

 

about

 

the

 

singularity:

 

some

 

see

 

it

 

as

 

a

 

likely

 

scenario,

 

others

 

believe

 

that

 

it

 

is

 

more

 

probable

 

that

 

there

 

will

 

never

 

be

 

any

 

very

 

sudden

 

and

 

dramatic

 

changes

 

as

 

the

 

result

 

of

 

progress

 

in

 

artificial

 

intelligence.

 

                                                        

22

 

(Moore

 

1965).

 

23

 

(Good

 

1965).

 

24

 

(Vinge

 

1993).

 

 

9

background image

 

The

 

singularity

 

idea

 

also

 

comes

 

in

 

a

 

somewhat

 

different

 

eschatological

 

version,

 

which

 

traces

 

its

 

lineage

 

to

 

the

 

writings

 

of

 

Pierre

 

Teilhard

 

de

 

Chardin,

 

a

 

paleontologist

 

and

 

Jesuit

 

theologian

 

who

 

saw

 

an

 

evolutionary

 

telos

 

in

 

the

 

development

 

of

 

an

 

encompassing

 

noosphere

 

(a

 

global

 

consciousness)

 

–

 

via

 

physicist

 

Frank

 

Tipler,

 

who

 

argued

 

that

 

advanced

 

civilizations

 

might

 

come

 

to

 

have

 

a

 

defining

 

influence

 

on

 

the

 

future

 

evolution

 

of

 

the

 

cosmos,

 

and,

 

in

 

the

 

final

 

moments

 

of

 

the

 

Big

 

Crunch,

 

might

 

manage

 

to

 

extract

 

an

 

infinite

 

number

 

of

 

computations

 

by

 

harnessing

 

the

 

sheer

 

energy

 

of

 

the

 

collapsing

 

matter.

25,26

 

However,

 

while

 

these

 

ideas

 

might

 

appeal

 

to

 

those

 

who

 

fancy

 

a

 

marriage

 

between

 

mysticism

 

and

 

science,

 

they

 

have

 

not

 

caught

 

on

 

either

 

among

 

transhumanists

 

or

 

the

 

larger

 

scientific

 

community.

 

Current

 

cosmological

 

theories

 

indicate

 

that

 

the

 

universe

 

will

 

continue

 

to

 

expand

 

forever

 

(falsifying

 

Tipler’s

 

prediction).

 

But

 

the

 

more

 

general

 

point

 

that

 

the

 

transhumanist

 

might

 

make

 

in

 

this

 

context

 

is

 

that

 

we

 

need

 

to

 

learn

 

to

 

think

 

about

 

“big

â€

picture

 

questionsâ€

 

without

 

resorting

 

to

 

wishful

 

thinking

 

or

 

mysticism.

 

Big

â€

picture

 

questions,

 

including

 

ones

 

about

 

our

 

place

 

in

 

the

 

world

 

and

 

the

 

long

â€

term

 

fate

 

of

 

intelligent

 

life

 

are

 

part

 

of

 

transhumanism;

 

however,

 

these

 

questions

 

should

 

be

 

addressed

 

in

 

a

 

sober,

 

disinterested

 

way,

 

using

 

critical

 

reason

 

and

 

our

 

best

 

available

 

scientific

 

evidence.

 

One

 

reason

 

why

 

such

 

questions

 

are

 

of

 

transhumanist

 

interest

 

is

 

that

 

their

 

answers

 

might

 

affect

 

what

 

outcomes

 

we

 

should

 

expect

 

from

 

our

 

own

 

technological

 

development,

 

and

 

therefore

 

–

 

indirectly

 

–

 

what

 

policies

 

it

 

makes

 

sense

 

for

 

humanity

 

to

 

pursue.

 

 

In

 

1986,

 

Eric

 

Drexler

 

published

 

Engines

 

of

 

Creation

,

 

the

 

first

 

book

â€

length

 

exposition

 

of

 

molecular

 

manufacturing.

27

 

(The

 

possibility

 

of

 

nanotechnology

 

had

 

been

 

anticipated

 

by

 

Nobel

 

laureate

 

physicist

 

Richard

 

Feynman

 

in

 

his

 

famous

 

after

â€

dinner

 

address

 

in

 

1959

 

entitled

 

“There

 

is

 

Plenty

 

of

 

Room

 

at

 

the

 

Bottomâ€.

28

)

 

In

 

this

 

seminal

 

work,

 

Drexler

 

not

 

only

 

argued

 

for

 

the

 

feasibility

 

of

 

assembler

â€

based

 

nanotechnology

 

but

 

also

 

explored

 

its

 

consequences

 

and

 

began

 

charting

 

the

 

strategic

 

challenges

 

posed

 

by

 

its

 

development.

 

Drexler’s

 

later

 

book

 

Nanosystems

 

(1992)

 

supplied

 

a

 

more

 

technical

 

analysis

 

that

 

seemed

 

to

 

confirm

 

his

 

original

 

conclusions.

29

 

To

 

prepare

 

the

 

world

 

for

 

nanotechnology

 

and

 

work

 

towards

 

its

 

safe

 

implementation,

 

he

 

founded

 

the

 

Foresight

 

Institute

 

together

 

with

 

his

 

then

 

wife,

 

Christine

 

Peterson,

 

in

 

1986.

 

 

                                                        

25

 

(Teilhard

 

de

 

Chardin

 

1964).

 

26

 

(Tipler

 

1994).

 

27

 

(Drexler

 

1985).

 

28

 

(Feynman

 

1960).

 

29

 

(Drexler

 

1992).

 

 

10

background image

In

 

the

 

last

 

several

 

years,

 

nanotechnology

 

has

 

become

 

big

 

business,

 

with

 

worldwide

 

research

 

funding

 

amounting

 

to

 

billions

 

of

 

dollars.

 

Yet

 

little

 

of

 

this

 

work

 

fits

 

Drexler’s

 

ambitious

 

vision

 

of

 

nanotechnology

 

as

 

an

 

assembler

â€

based,

 

near

â€

universal,

 

construction

 

technology.

 

The

 

mainstream

 

nanotechnology

 

community

 

has

 

sought

 

to

 

distance

 

itself

 

from

 

Drexler’s

 

claims.

 

The

 

chemist

 

Richard

 

Smalley

 

(another

 

Nobel

 

laureate)

 

has

 

debated

 

Drexler,

 

asserting

 

that

 

non

â€

biological

 

molecular

 

assemblers

 

are

 

impossible.

30

 

To

 

date,

 

however,

 

no

 

technical

 

critique

 

of

 

Drexler’s

 

work

 

in

 

the

 

published

 

literature

 

has

 

found

 

any

 

significant

 

flaws

 

in

 

his

 

reasoning.

 

If

 

molecular

 

nanotechnology

 

is

 

indeed

 

physically

 

possible,

 

as

 

Drexler

 

main

the

 

question

 

becomes

 

just

 

how

 

difficult

 

it

 

will

 

be

 

to

 

develop

 

it,

 

and

 

how

 

long

 

it

 

will

 

take.

 

These

 

issues

 

are

 

very

 

difficult

 

to

 

settle

 

in

 

adv

tains,

 

ance.

 

                                                       

 

If

 

molecular

 

nanotechnology

 

could

 

be

 

developed

 

as

 

Drexler

 

envisions

 

it,

 

it

 

would

 

have

 

momentous

 

ramifications:

 

 

Coal

 

and

 

diamonds,

 

sand

 

and

 

computer

 

chips,

 

cancer

 

and

 

healthy

 

tissue:

 

throughout

 

history,

 

variations

 

in

 

the

 

arrangement

 

of

 

atoms

 

have

 

distinguished

 

the

 

cheap

 

from

 

the

 

cherished,

 

the

 

diseased

 

from

 

the

 

healthy.

 

Arranged

 

one

 

way,

 

atoms

 

make

 

up

 

soil,

 

air,

 

and

 

water

 

arranged

 

another,

 

they

 

make

 

up

 

ripe

 

strawberries.

 

Arranged

 

one

 

way,

 

they

 

make

 

up

 

homes

 

and

 

fresh

 

air;

 

arranged

 

another,

 

they

 

make

 

up

 

ash

 

and

 

smoke.

31

 

 

Molecular

 

nanotechnology

 

would

 

enable

 

us

 

to

 

transform

 

coal

 

into

 

diamonds,

 

sand

 

into

 

supercomputers,

 

and

 

to

 

remove

 

pollution

 

from

 

the

 

air

 

and

 

tumors

 

from

 

healthy

 

tissue.

 

In

 

its

 

mature

 

form,

 

it

 

could

 

help

 

us

 

abolish

 

most

 

disease

 

and

 

aging,

 

make

 

possible

 

the

 

reanimation

 

of

 

cryonics

 

patients,

 

enable

 

affordable

 

space

 

colonization,

 

and

 

–

 

more

 

ominously

 

–

 

lead

 

to

 

the

 

rapid

 

creation

 

of

 

vast

 

arsenals

 

of

 

lethal

 

or

 

non

â€

lethal

 

weapons.

 

 

Another

 

hypothetical

 

technology

 

that

 

would

 

have

 

a

 

revolutionary

 

impact

 

is

 

uploading,

 

the

 

transfer

 

of

 

a

 

human

 

mind

 

to

 

a

 

computer.

 

This

 

would

 

involve

 

the

 

following

 

steps:

 

First,

 

create

 

a

 

sufficiently

 

detailed

 

scan

 

of

 

a

 

particular

 

human

 

brain,

 

perhaps

 

by

 

deconstructing

 

it

 

with

 

nanobots

 

or

 

by

 

feeding

 

thin

 

slices

 

of

 

brain

 

tissues

 

into

 

powerful

 

microscopes

 

for

 

automatic

 

image

 

analysis.

 

Second,

 

from

 

this

 

scan,

 

reconstruct

 

the

 

neuronal

 

network

 

that

 

the

 

brain

 

implemented,

 

and

 

combine

 

this

 

with

 

computational

 

models

 

of

 

the

 

different

 

types

 

of

 

neurons.

 

Third,

 

emulate

 

the

 

whole

 

computational

 

structure

 

on

 

a

 

powerful

 

supercomputer.

 

If

 

successful,

 

the

 

procedure

 

would

 

result

 

in

 

the

 

original

 

mind,

 

with

 

memory

 

and

 

personality

 

intact,

 

being

 

transferred

 

to

 

the

 

computer

 

where

 

it

 

would

 

then

 

exist

 

as

 

software;

 

and

 

it

 

could

 

 

30

 

(Drexler

 

and

 

Smalley

 

1993).

 

31

 

(Drexler

 

1985),

 

p.

 

3.

 

 

11

background image

either

 

inhabit

 

a

 

robot

 

body

 

or

 

live

 

in

 

a

 

virtual

 

reality.

32

 

While

 

it

 

is

 

often

 

thought

 

that,

 

under

 

suitable

 

circumstances,

 

the

 

upload

 

would

 

be

 

conscious

 

and

 

that

 

the

 

original

 

person

 

would

 

have

 

survived

 

the

 

transfer

 

to

 

the

 

new

 

medium,

 

individual

 

transhumanists

 

take

 

different

 

views

 

on

 

these

 

philosophical

 

matters.

 

 

If

 

either

 

superintelligence,

 

or

 

molecular

 

nanotechnology,

 

or

 

uploading,

 

or

 

some

 

other

 

technology

 

of

 

a

 

similarly

 

revolutionary

 

kind

 

is

 

developed,

 

the

 

human

 

condition

 

could

 

clearly

 

be

 

radically

 

transformed.

 

Even

 

if

 

one

 

believed

 

that

 

the

 

probability

 

of

 

this

 

happening

 

any

 

time

 

soon

 

is

 

quite

 

small,

 

these

 

prospects

 

would

 

nevertheless

 

merit

 

serious

 

attention

 

in

 

view

 

of

 

their

 

extreme

 

impact.

 

However,

 

transhumanism

 

does

 

not

 

depend

 

on

 

the

 

feasibility

 

of

 

such

 

radical

 

technologies.

 

Virtual

 

reality;

 

preimplantation

 

genetic

 

diagnosis;

 

genetic

 

engineering;

 

pharmaceuticals

 

that

 

improve

 

memory,

 

concentration,

 

wakefulness,

 

and

 

mood;

 

performance

â€

enhancing

 

drugs;

 

cosmetic

 

surgery;

 

sex

 

change

 

operations;

 

prosthetics;

 

anti

â€

aging

 

medicine;

 

closer

 

human

â€

computer

 

interfaces:

 

these

 

technologies

 

are

 

already

 

here

 

or

 

can

 

be

 

expected

 

within

 

the

 

next

 

few

 

decades.

 

The

 

combination

 

of

 

these

 

technological

 

capabilities,

 

as

 

they

 

mature,

 

could

 

profoundly

 

transform

 

the

 

human

 

condition.

 

The

 

transhumanist

 

agenda,

 

which

 

is

 

to

 

make

 

such

 

enhancement

 

options

 

safely

 

available

 

to

 

all

 

persons,

 

will

 

become

 

increasingly

 

relevant

 

and

 

practical

 

in

 

the

 

coming

 

years

 

as

 

these

 

and

 

other

 

anticipated

 

technologies

 

come

 

online.

  

 

4.

 

The

 

growth

 

of

 

grassroots

 

Benjamin

 

Franklin

 

wished

 

to

 

be

 

preserved

 

in

 

a

 

cask

 

of

 

Madeira

 

and

 

later

 

recalled

 

to

 

life,

 

and

 

regretted

 

that

 

he

 

was

 

living

 

too

 

near

 

the

 

infancy

 

of

 

science

 

for

 

this

 

to

 

be

 

possible.

 

Since

 

then,

 

science

 

has

 

grown

 

up

 

a

 

bit.

 

In

 

1962,

 

Robert

 

Ettinger

 

published

 

the

 

book,

 

The

 

Prospect

 

of

 

Immortality

,

 

which

 

launched

 

the

 

idea

 

of

 

cryonic

 

suspension.

33

 

Ettinger

 

argued

 

that

 

as

 

medical

 

technology

 

seems

 

to

 

be

 

constantly

 

progressing,

 

and

 

since

 

science

 

has

 

discover

that

 

chemical

 

activity

 

comes

 

to

 

a

 

complete

 

halt

 

at

 

low

â€

enough

 

temperatures,

 

it

 

should

 

be

 

possible

 

to

 

freeze

 

a

 

person

 

today

 

(in

 

liquid

 

nitrogen)

 

and

 

preserve

 

the

 

body

 

until

 

a

 

tim

when

 

technology

 

is

 

advanced

 

enough

 

to

 

repair

 

the

 

freezing

 

damage

 

and

 

reverse

 

the

 

original

 

cause

 

of

 

deanimation.

 

Cryonics,

 

Ettinger

 

believed,

 

offered

 

a

 

ticket

 

to

 

the

 

fu

ed

 

e

 

ture.

 

                                                       

 

Alas,

 

the

 

masses

 

did

 

not

 

line

 

up

 

for

 

the

 

ride.

 

Cryonics

 

has

 

remained

 

a

 

fringe

 

alternative

 

to

 

more

 

traditional

 

methods

 

of

 

treating

 

the

 

diseased,

 

such

 

as

 

cremation

 

and

 

burial.

 

The

 

practice

 

of

 

cryonics

 

was

 

not

 

integrated

 

into

 

the

 

mainstream

 

clinical

 

setting

 

and

 

was

 

instead

 

conducted

 

on

 

the

 

cheap

 

by

 

a

 

small

 

number

 

of

 

enthusiasts.

 

Two

 

early

 

cryonics

 

organizations

 

 

32

 

(Bostrom

 

2003).

 

33

 

(Ettinger

 

1964).

 

 

12

background image

went

 

bankrupt,

 

allowing

 

their

 

patients

 

to

 

thaw

 

out.

 

At

 

that

 

point,

 

the

 

problem

 

of

 

massive

 

cellular

 

damage

 

that

 

occurs

 

when

 

ice

 

crystals

 

form

 

in

 

the

 

body

 

also

 

became

 

more

 

widely

 

known.

 

As

 

a

 

result,

 

cryonics

 

acquired

 

a

 

reputation

 

as

 

a

 

macabre

 

scam.

 

The

 

media

 

controversy

 

over

 

the

 

suspension

 

of

 

baseball

 

star

 

Ted

 

Williams

 

in

 

2002

 

showed

 

that

 

public

 

perception

 

of

 

cryonics

 

has

 

not

 

changed

 

much

 

over

 

the

 

past

 

decades.

 

 

Despite

 

its

 

image

 

problem

 

and

 

its

 

early

 

failures

 

of

 

implementation,

 

the

 

cryonics

 

community

 

continues

 

to

 

be

 

active

 

and

 

it

 

counts

 

among

 

its

 

members

 

several

 

eminent

 

scientists

 

and

 

intellectuals.

 

Suspension

 

protocols

 

have

 

been

 

improved,

 

and

 

the

 

infusion

 

of

 

cryoprotectants

 

prior

 

to

 

freezing

 

to

 

suppress

 

the

 

formation

 

of

 

ice

 

crystals

 

has

 

become

 

standard

 

practice.

 

The

 

prospect

 

of

 

nanotechnology

 

has

 

given

 

a

 

more

 

concrete

 

shape

 

to

 

the

 

hypothesized

 

future

 

technology

 

that

 

could

 

enable

 

reanimation.

 

There

 

are

 

currently

 

two

 

organizations

 

that

 

offer

 

full

â€

service

 

suspension,

 

the

 

Alcor

 

Life

 

Extension

 

Foundation

 

(founded

 

in

 

1972)

 

and

 

the

 

Cryonics

 

Institute

 

(founded

 

in

 

1976).

 

Alcor

 

has

 

recently

 

introduced

 

a

 

new

 

suspension

 

method,

 

which

 

relies

 

on

 

a

 

process

 

known

 

as

 

“vitrificationâ€,

 

which

 

further

 

reduces

 

micro

â€

structural

 

damage

 

during

 

suspension.

 

 

In

 

a

 

later

 

work,

 

Man

 

into

 

Superman

 

(1972),

 

Ettinger

 

discussed

 

a

 

number

 

of

 

conceivable

 

technological

 

improvements

 

of

 

the

 

human

 

organism,

 

continuing

 

the

 

tradition

 

started

 

by

 

Haldane

 

and

 

Bernal.

34

 

 

Another

 

early

 

transhumanist

 

was

 

F.

 

M.

 

Esfandiary,

 

who

 

later

 

changed

 

his

 

name

 

to

 

FM

â€

2030.

 

One

 

of

 

the

 

first

 

professors

 

of

 

future

 

studies,

 

FM

 

taught

 

at

 

the

 

New

 

School

 

for

 

Social

 

Research

 

in

 

New

 

York

 

in

 

the

 

1960s

 

and

 

formed

 

a

 

group

 

of

 

optimistic

 

futurists

 

known

 

as

 

the

 

UpWingers.

 

 

Who

 

are

 

the

 

new

 

revolutionaries

 

of

 

our

 

time?

 

They

 

are

 

the

 

geneticists,

 

biologists,

 

physicists,

 

cryonologists,

 

biotechnologists,

 

nuclear

 

scientists,

 

cosmologists,

 

radio

 

astronomers,

 

cosmonauts,

 

social

 

scientists,

 

youth

 

corps

 

volunteers,

 

internationalists,

 

humanists,

 

science

â€

fiction

 

writers,

 

normative

 

thinkers,

 

inventors…

 

They

 

and

 

others

 

are

 

revolutionizing

 

the

 

human

 

condition

 

in

 

a

 

fundamental

 

way.

 

Their

 

achievements

 

and

 

goals

 

go

 

far

 

beyond

 

the

 

most

 

radical

 

ideologies

 

of

 

the

 

Old

 

Order.

35

 

 

In

 

his

 

book

 

Are

 

you

 

a

 

transhuman?

 

(1989),

 

FM

 

described

 

what

 

he

 

regarded

 

as

 

the

 

signs

 

of

 

the

 

emergence

 

of

 

the

 

“transhumanâ€.

36

 

In

 

FM’s

 

terminology,

 

a

 

transhuman

 

is

 

a

 

“transitional

 

                                                        

34

 

(Ettinger

 

1972).

 

35

 

(Esfandiary

 

1970).

 

36

 

(FM

â€

2030

 

1989).

 

 

13

background image

human,â€

 

someone

 

who

 

by

 

virtue

 

of

 

their

 

technology

 

usage,

 

cultural

 

values,

 

and

 

lifestyle

 

constitutes

 

an

 

evolutionary

 

link

 

to

 

the

 

coming

 

era

 

of

 

posthumanity.

 

The

 

signs

 

that

 

FM

 

saw

 

as

 

indicative

 

of

 

transhuman

 

status

 

included

 

prostheses,

 

plastic

 

surgery,

 

intensive

 

use

 

of

 

telecommunications,

 

a

 

cosmopolitan

 

outlook

 

and

 

a

 

globetrotting

 

lifestyle,

 

androgyny,

 

mediated

 

reproduction

 

(such

 

as

 

in

 

vitro

 

fertilization),

 

absence

 

of

 

religious

 

belief,

 

and

 

a

 

rejection

 

of

 

traditional

 

family

 

values.

 

However,

 

it

 

was

 

never

 

satisfactorily

 

explained

 

why

 

somebody

 

who,

 

say,

 

rejects

 

family

 

values,

 

has

 

a

 

nose

 

job,

 

and

 

spends

 

a

 

lot

 

of

 

time

 

on

 

jet

 

planes

 

is

 

in

 

closer

 

proximity

 

to

 

posthumanity

 

than

 

the

 

rest

 

of

 

us.

 

 

In

 

the

 

1970s

 

and

 

1980s,

 

many

 

organizations

 

sprang

 

up

 

that

 

focused

 

on

 

a

 

particular

 

topic

 

such

 

as

 

life

 

extension,

 

cryonics,

 

space

 

colonization,

 

science

 

fiction,

 

and

 

futurism.

 

These

 

groups

 

were

 

often

 

isolated

 

from

 

one

 

another,

 

and

 

whatever

 

shared

 

views

 

and

 

values

 

they

 

had

 

did

 

not

 

yet

 

amount

 

to

 

any

 

unified

 

worldview.

 

Ed

 

Regis’s

 

Great

 

Mambo

 

Chicken

 

and

 

the

 

Transhuman

 

Condition

 

(1990)

 

took

 

a

 

humorous

 

look

 

at

 

these

 

proto

â€

transhumanist

 

fringes,

 

which

 

included

 

eccentric

 

and

 

otherwise

 

intelligent

 

individuals

 

trying

 

to

 

build

 

space

 

rockets

 

in

 

their

 

backyards

 

or

 

experimenting

 

with

 

biofeedback

 

machines

 

and

 

psychedelic

 

drugs,

 

as

 

well

 

as

 

scientists

 

pursuing

 

more

 

serious

 

lines

 

of

 

work

 

but

 

who

 

had

 

imbibed

 

too

 

deeply

 

of

 

the

 

Californian

 

spirit.

37

 

 

In

 

1988,

 

the

 

first

 

issue

 

of

 

the

 

Extropy

 

Magazine

 

was

 

published

 

by

 

Max

 

More

 

and

 

Tom

 

Morrow,

 

and

 

in

 

1992

 

they

 

founded

 

the

 

Extropy

 

Institute

 

(the

 

term

 

“extropyâ€

 

being

 

coined

 

as

 

a

 

metaphorical

 

opposite

 

of

 

entropy).

 

The

 

Institute

 

served

 

as

 

a

 

catalyst

 

that

 

brought

 

together

 

disparate

 

groups

 

of

 

people

 

with

 

futuristic

 

ideas

 

and

 

facilitated

 

the

 

formation

 

of

 

novel

 

memetic

 

compounds.

 

The

 

Institute

 

ran

 

a

 

series

 

of

 

conferences,

 

but

 

perhaps

 

most

 

important

 

was

 

the

 

extropians

 

mailing

 

list,

 

an

 

online

 

discussion

 

forum

 

where

 

new

 

ideas

 

were

 

shared

 

and

 

debated.

 

In

 

the

 

mid

â€

nineties,

 

many

 

got

 

first

 

exposure

 

to

 

transhumanist

 

views

 

from

 

the

 

Extropy

 

Institute’s

 

listserve.

 

 

More

 

had

 

immigrated

 

to

 

California

 

from

 

Britain

 

after

 

changing

 

his

 

name

 

from

 

Max

 

O’Connor.

 

Of

 

his

 

new

 

name,

 

he

 

said:

 

 

It

 

seemed

 

to

 

really

 

encapsulate

 

the

 

essence

 

of

 

what

 

my

 

goal

 

is:

 

always

 

to

 

improve,

 

never

 

to

 

be

 

static.

 

I

 

was

 

going

 

to

 

get

 

better

 

at

 

everything,

 

become

 

smarter,

 

fitter,

 

and

 

healthier.

 

It

 

would

 

be

 

a

 

constant

 

reminder

 

to

 

keep

 

moving

 

forward.

38

 

 

                                                        

37

 

(Regis

 

1990).

 

38

 

(Regis

 

1994).

 

 

14

background image

Max

 

More

 

wrote

 

the

 

first

 

definition

 

of

 

transhumanism

 

in

 

its

 

modern

 

sense,

 

and

 

created

 

his

 

own

 

distinctive

 

brand

 

of

 

transhumanism,

 

“extropianism,â€

 

which

 

emphasized

 

the

 

principles

 

of

 

“boundless

 

expansion,â€

 

“self

â€

transformation,â€

 

“dynamic

 

optimism,â€

 

“intelligent

 

technology,â€

 

and

 

“spontaneous

 

orderâ€.

 

Originally,

 

extropianism

 

had

 

a

 

clear

 

libertarian

 

flavor,

 

but

 

in

 

later

 

years

 

More

 

has

 

distanced

 

himself

 

from

 

this

 

ingredient,

 

replacing

 

“spontaneous

 

orderâ€

 

with

 

“open

 

society,â€

 

a

 

principle

 

that

 

opposes

 

authoritarian

 

social

 

control

 

and

 

promotes

 

decentralization

 

of

 

power

 

and

 

responsibility.

 

Natasha

 

Vita

â€

More

 

is

 

the

 

Extropy

 

Institute’s

 

current

 

president.

 

She

 

is

 

an

 

artist

 

and

 

designer,

 

and

 

has

 

over

 

the

 

years

 

issued

 

a

 

number

 

of

 

manifestos

 

on

 

transhumanist

 

and

 

extropic

 

art.

 

The

 

Extropy

 

Institute’s

 

conferences

 

and

 

mailing

 

list

 

also

 

served

 

as

 

a

 

hangout

 

place

 

for

 

some

 

people

 

who

 

liked

 

to

 

discuss

 

futuristic

 

ideas

 

but

 

who

 

were

 

not

 

necessarily

 

joiners.

 

Those

 

who

 

were

 

around

 

in

 

the

 

mid

â€

nineties

 

will

 

remember

 

individuals

 

such

 

as

 

Anders

 

Sandberg,

 

Alexander

 

“Sashaâ€

 

Chislenko,

 

Hal

 

Finney,

 

and

 

Robin

 

Hanson

 

from

 

among

 

the

 

more

 

thoughtful

 

regulars

 

in

 

the

 

transhumanist

 

milieu

 

at

 

the

 

time.

 

An

 

enormous

 

amount

 

of

 

discussion

 

about

 

transhumanism

 

has

 

taken

 

place

 

on

 

various

 

email

 

lists

 

in

 

the

 

past

 

decade.

 

The

 

quality

 

of

 

postings

 

has

 

been

 

varied

 

(putting

 

it

 

mildly).

 

Yet

 

at

 

their

 

best,

 

these

 

online

 

conversations

 

explored

 

ideas

 

about

 

the

 

implications

 

of

 

future

 

technologies

 

that

 

were,

 

in

 

some

 

respects,

 

far

 

advanced

 

over

 

what

 

could

 

be

 

found

 

in

 

printed

 

books

 

or

 

journals.

 

The

 

Internet

 

played

 

an

 

important

 

role

 

in

 

incubating

 

modern

 

transhumanism

 

by

 

facilitating

 

these

 

meetings

 

of

 

minds

 

–

 

and

 

perhaps

 

more

 

indirectly,

 

too,

 

via

 

the

 

“irrational

 

exuberanceâ€

 

that

 

pervaded

 

the

 

dot

â€

com

 

era?

 

 

The

 

World

 

Transhumanist

 

Association

 

was

 

founded

 

in

 

early

 

1998

 

by

 

Nick

 

Bostrom

 

and

 

David

 

Pearce,

 

to

 

provide

 

a

 

general

 

organizational

 

basis

 

for

 

all

 

transhumanist

 

groups

 

and

 

interests,

 

across

 

the

 

political

 

spectrum.

 

The

 

aim

 

was

 

also

 

to

 

develop

 

a

 

more

 

mature

 

and

 

academically

 

respectable

 

form

 

of

 

transhumanism,

 

freed

 

from

 

the

 

“cultishnessâ€

 

which,

 

at

 

least

 

in

 

the

 

eyes

 

of

 

some

 

critics,

 

had

 

afflicted

 

some

 

of

 

its

 

earlier

 

convocations.

 

The

 

two

 

founding

 

documents

 

of

 

the

 

WTA

 

were

 

the

 

Transhumanist

 

Declaration

 

(see

 

appendix),

 

and

 

the

 

Transhumanist

 

FAQ

 

(v.

 

1.0).

 

The

 

Declaration

 

was

 

intended

 

as

 

a

 

concise

 

consensus

 

statement

 

of

 

the

 

basic

 

principle

 

of

 

transhumanism.

 

The

 

FAQ

 

was

 

also

 

a

 

consensus

 

or

 

near

â€

consensus

 

document,

 

but

 

it

 

was

 

more

 

ambitious

 

in

 

its

 

philosophical

 

scope

 

in

 

that

 

it

 

developed

 

a

 

number

 

of

 

themes

 

that

 

had

 

previously

 

been,

 

at

 

most,

 

implicit

 

in

 

the

 

movement.

 

More

 

than

 

fifty

 

people

 

contributed

 

comments

 

on

 

drafts

 

of

 

the

 

FAQ.

 

The

 

document

 

was

 

produced

 

by

 

                                                        

39

 

(More

 

2003).

 

40

 

(Vita

â€

More

 

2002).

 

41

 

(WTA

 

2002).

 

 

15

background image

Bostrom

 

but

 

major

 

parts

 

and

 

ideas

 

were

 

also

 

contributed

 

by

 

several

 

others,

 

including

 

the

 

British

 

utilitarian

 

thinker

 

David

 

Pearce,

 

Max

 

More,

 

the

 

American

 

feminist

 

and

 

disability

 

rights

 

activist

 

Kathryn

 

Aegis,

 

and

 

the

 

walking

 

encyclopedia

 

Anders

 

Sandberg,

 

who

 

was

 

at

 

the

 

time

 

a

 

neuroscience

 

student

 

in

 

Sweden.

 

 

David

 

Pearce

 

has

 

also

 

developed

 

his

 

own

 

distinctive

 

flavor

 

of

 

transhumanism

 

based

 

on

 

an

 

ethic

 

of

 

hedonistic

 

utilitarianism.

 

Pearce

 

argues,

 

in

 

The

 

Hedonistic

 

Imperative

,

 

for

 

an

 

ambitious

 

program

 

to

 

eliminate

 

suffering

 

in

 

both

 

human

 

and

 

non

â€

human

 

animals

 

by

 

means

 

of

 

advanced

 

neuro

â€

technology

 

(in

 

the

 

short

 

term

 

pharmaceuticals,

 

in

 

the

 

longer

 

term

 

perhaps

 

genetic

 

engineering).

42

 

In

 

parallel

 

with

 

this

 

negative

 

effort

 

to

 

abolish

 

suffering,

 

he

 

proposes

 

a

 

positive

 

program

 

of

 

“paradise

 

engineeringâ€

 

in

 

which

 

sentient

 

beings

 

would

 

be

 

redesigned

 

to

 

enable

 

everybody

 

to

 

experience

 

of

 

unprecedented

 

levels

 

of

 

well

â€

being.

 

In

 

Pearce’s

 

utopia,

 

our

 

motivation

 

system

 

would

 

run

 

on

 

“gradients

 

of

 

blissâ€

 

instead

 

of

 

the

 

current

 

pleasure

â€

pain

 

axis.

 

 

The

 

WTA’s

 

membership

 

grew

 

rapidly,

 

and

 

local

 

chapters

 

mushroomed

 

around

 

the

 

world.

 

Activities

 

focused

 

mainly

 

on

 

Internet

 

discussion,

 

development

 

of

 

documents,

 

representation

 

in

 

the

 

media,

 

organizing

 

of

 

an

 

annual

 

TransVision

 

conference,

 

and

 

publication

 

of

 

the

 

scholarly

 

online

 

Journal

 

of

 

Transhumanism

 

(later

 

renamed

 

to

 

“Journal

 

of

 

Evolution

 

and

 

Technologyâ€).

 

 

In

 

the

 

first

 

few

 

years

 

of

 

its

 

existence,

 

the

 

WTA

 

was

 

a

 

very

 

loosely

 

and

 

informally

 

organized

 

structure.

 

It

 

entered

 

its

 

next

 

phase

 

after

 

a

 

meeting

 

in

 

2001

 

between

 

James

 

Hughes

 

(a

 

sociologist

 

at

 

Trinity

 

College

 

in

 

Hartford

 

Connecticut),

 

Mark

 

Walker

 

(a

 

philosopher

 

at

 

the

 

University

 

of

 

Toronto,

 

then

 

the

 

editor

 

of

 

the

 

Journal

 

of

 

Transhumanism),

 

and

 

Bostrom

 

(who

 

was

 

at

 

the

 

time

 

teaching

 

at

 

Yale).

 

Hughes

 

was

 

elected

 

Secretary

 

and

 

turned

 

his

 

organizing

 

skills

 

and

 

energy

 

to

 

the

 

task.

 

Within

 

short

 

order,

 

the

 

WTA

 

adopted

 

a

 

constitution,

 

incorporated

 

as

 

a

 

non

â€

profit,

 

and

 

began

 

building

 

up

 

a

 

vigorous

 

international

 

network

 

of

 

local

 

groups

 

and

 

volunteers.

 

Currently,

 

the

 

WTA

 

has

 

approximately

 

3,000

 

members

 

from

 

more

 

than

 

100

 

countries,

 

and

 

it

 

pursues

 

a

 

wide

 

range

 

of

 

activities,

 

all

 

volunteer

â€

driven.

 

 

A

 

number

 

of

 

related

 

organizations

 

have

 

also

 

cropped

 

up

 

in

 

recent

 

years,

 

focusing

 

more

 

narrowly

 

on

 

particular

 

transhumanist

 

issues,

 

such

 

as

 

life

â€

extension,

 

artificial

 

intelligence,

 

or

 

the

 

legal

 

implications

 

of

 

“converging

 

technologiesâ€

 

(nano

â€

bio

â€

info

â€

neuro

 

technologies).

 

The

 

Institute

 

for

 

Ethics

 

and

 

Emerging

 

Technologies,

 

a

 

non

â€

profit

 

think

 

tank,

 

was

 

established

 

in

 

2004,

 

to

 

“promote

 

the

 

ethical

 

use

 

of

 

technology

 

to

 

expand

 

human

 

capacitiesâ€.

 

 

                                                        

42

 

(Pearce

 

2004).

 

 

16

background image

5.

 

The

 

academic

 

frontier

 

Over

 

the

 

past

 

couple

 

of

 

decades,

 

academia

 

has

 

picked

 

up

 

the

 

ball

 

and

 

started

 

to

 

analyze

 

various

 

“transhumanist

 

matters,â€

 

both

 

normative

 

and

 

positive.

 

The

 

contributions

 

are

 

far

 

too

 

many

 

to

 

comprehensively

 

describe

 

here,

 

so

 

we

 

will

 

pick

 

out

 

just

 

a

 

few

 

threads,

 

beginning

 

with

 

ethics.

 

 

For

 

most

 

of

 

its

 

history,

 

moral

 

philosophy

 

did

 

not

 

shy

 

away

 

from

 

addressing

 

practical

 

problems.

 

In

 

the

 

early

 

and

 

mid

â€

parts

 

of

 

the

 

twentieth

 

century,

 

during

 

heydays

 

of

 

logical

 

positivism,

 

applied

 

ethics

 

became

 

a

 

backwater

 

as

 

moral

 

philosophers

 

concentrated

 

on

 

linguistic

 

or

 

meta

â€

ethical

 

problems.

 

Since

 

then,

 

however,

 

practical

 

ethics

 

has

 

reemerged

 

as

 

a

 

field

 

of

 

academic

 

inquiry.

 

The

 

comeback

 

started

 

in

 

medical

 

ethics.

 

Revelations

 

of

 

the

 

horrific

 

experiments

 

that

 

the

 

Nazis

 

had

 

conducted

 

on

 

human

 

subjects

 

in

 

the

 

name

 

of

 

science

 

led

 

to

 

the

 

adoption

 

of

 

the

 

Nuremberg

 

code

 

(1947)

 

and

 

the

 

Declaration

 

of

 

Helsinki

 

(1964),

 

which

 

laid

 

down

 

strict

 

safeguards

 

for

 

medical

 

experimentation,

 

emphasizing

 

the

 

need

 

for

 

patient

 

consent.

43,44

 

But

 

the

 

rise

 

of

 

the

 

modern

 

health

 

care

 

system

 

spawned

 

new

 

ethical

 

dilemmas

 

–

 

turning

 

off

 

life

â€

support,

 

organ

 

donation,

 

resource

 

allocation,

 

abortion,

 

advance

 

directives,

 

doctor

â€

patient

 

relationships,

 

protocols

 

for

 

obtaining

 

informed

 

consent

 

and

 

for

 

dealing

 

with

 

incompetent

 

patients.

 

In

 

the

 

1970s,

 

a

 

broader

 

kind

 

of

 

enquiry

 

began

 

to

 

emerge,

 

stimulated

 

particularly

 

by

 

developments

 

in

 

assisted

 

reproduction

 

and

 

genetics.

 

This

 

field

 

became

 

known

 

as

 

bioethics.

 

Many

 

of

 

the

 

ethical

 

issues

 

most

 

directly

 

linked

 

to

 

transhumanism

 

would

 

now

 

fall

 

under

 

this

 

rubric,

 

although

 

other

 

normative

 

discourses

 

are

 

also

 

involved,

 

e.g.

 

population

 

ethics,

 

meta

â€

ethics,

 

political

 

philosophy,

 

and

 

bioethics’

 

younger

 

sisters

 

–

 

computer

 

ethics,

 

engineering

 

ethics,

 

environmental

 

ethics.

 

 

Bioethics

 

was

 

from

 

the

 

beginning

 

an

 

interdisciplinary

 

endeavor,

 

dominated

 

by

 

theologians,

 

legal

 

scholars,

 

physicians,

 

and,

 

increasingly,

 

philosophers,

 

with

 

occasional

 

participation

 

by

 

representatives

 

of

 

patients’

 

rights

 

groups,

 

disability

 

advocates,

 

and

 

other

 

interested

 

parties.

 

45

 

Lacking

 

a

 

clear

 

methodology,

 

and

 

operating

 

on

 

a

 

plain

 

often

 

swept

 

by

 

the

 

winds

 

of

 

political

 

or

 

religious

 

controversy,

 

the

 

standard

 

of

 

scholarship

 

has

 

frequently

 

been

 

underwhelming.

 

Despite

 

these

 

difficulties,

 

bioethics

 

burgeoned.

 

A

 

cynic

 

might

 

ascribe

 

this

 

accomplishment

 

to

 

the

 

ample

 

fertilization

 

that

 

the

 

field

 

received

 

from

 

a

 

number

 

of

 

pra

imperatives:

 

absolving

 

doctors

 

of

 

moral

 

dilemmas,

 

training

 

medical

 

students

 

to

 

behave,

 

enabling

 

hospital

 

boards

 

to

 

trumpet

 

their

 

commitment

 

to

 

the

 

highest

 

ethical

 

standards

 

o

care,

 

providing

 

sound

 

bites

 

for

 

the

 

mass

 

media,

 

and

 

allowing

 

politicians

 

to

 

cover

 

their

 

behinds

 

by

 

delegating

 

controversial

 

issues

 

to

 

ethics

 

committees.

 

But

 

a

 

kinder

 

gloss

 

is

 

ctical

 

f

 

                                                        

43

 

(Office

 

1949).

 

44

 

(World_Medical_Organization

 

1996).

 

45

 

See

 

(Jonsen

 

1998).

 

 

17

background image

possible:

 

decent

 

people

 

recognized

 

that

 

difficult

 

moral

 

problems

 

arose

 

in

 

modern

 

biomedicine,

 

that

 

these

 

problems

 

needed

 

to

 

be

 

addressed,

 

and

 

that

 

having

 

some

 

profession

scholars

 

trying

 

to

 

clarify

 

these

 

problems

 

in

 

some

 

sort

 

of

 

systematic

 

way

 

might

 

be

 

helpful.

 

While

 

higher

â€

caliber

 

scholarship

 

and

 

a

 

more

 

robust

 

methodology

 

would

 

be

 

nice,

 

in

 

the

 

meantime

al

 

 

we

 

make

 

the

 

most

 

of

 

what

 

we

 

have.

 

                                                       

 

Moral

 

philosophers

 

have

 

in

 

the

 

last

 

couple

 

of

 

decades

 

made

 

many

 

contributions

 

that

 

bear

 

on

 

the

 

ethics

 

of

 

human

 

transformation,

 

and

 

we

 

must

 

limit

 

ourselves

 

to

 

a

 

few

 

mentions.

 

Derek

 

Parfit’s

 

classic

 

Reasons

 

and

 

Persons

 

(1984)

 

discussed

 

many

 

relevant

 

normative

 

issues.

46

 

In

 

addition

 

to

 

personal

 

identity

 

and

 

foundational

 

ethical

 

theory,

 

this

 

book

 

treats

 

population

 

ethics,

 

person

â€

affecting

 

moral

 

principles,

 

and

 

duties

 

to

 

future

 

generations.

 

Although

 

Parfit’s

 

analysis

 

takes

 

place

 

on

 

an

 

idealized

 

level,

 

his

 

arguments

 

elucidate

 

many

 

moral

 

considerations

 

that

 

emerge

 

within

 

the

 

transhumanist

 

program.

 

 

Jonathan

 

Glover’s

 

What

 

Sort

 

of

 

People

 

Should

 

there

 

Be?

 

(1984)

 

addressed

 

technology

â€

enabled

 

human

â€

transformation

 

at

 

a

 

somewhat

 

more

 

concrete

 

level,

 

focusing

 

especially

 

on

 

genetics

 

and

 

various

 

technologies

 

that

 

could

 

increase

 

social

 

transparency.

 

Glover

 

gave

 

a

 

clear

 

and

 

balanced

 

analytic

 

treatment

 

of

 

these

 

issues

 

that

 

was

 

well

 

ahead

 

of

 

its

 

time.

 

His

 

general

 

conclusion

 

is

 

that

 

 

not

 

just

 

any

 

aspect

 

of

 

present

 

human

 

nature…

 

is

 

worth

 

preserving.

 

Rather

 

it

 

is

 

especially

 

those

 

features

 

which

 

contribute

 

to

 

self

â€

development

 

and

 

self

â€

expression,

 

to

 

certain

 

kinds

 

of

 

relationships,

 

and

 

to

 

the

 

development

 

of

 

our

 

consciousness

 

and

 

understanding.

 

And

 

some

 

of

 

these

 

features

 

may

 

be

 

extended

 

rather

 

than

 

threatened

 

by

 

technology.

47

 

 

Several

 

people

 

have

 

argued

 

for

 

principles

 

that

 

assert

 

some

 

kind

 

of

 

ethical

 

equivalence

 

between

 

environmental

 

and

 

genetic

 

interventions.

 

For

 

example,

 

Peter

 

Singer

 

has

 

proposed

 

the

 

“preventive

 

principleâ€:

 

 

For

 

any

 

condition

 

X,

 

if

 

it

 

would

 

be

 

a

 

form

 

of

 

child

 

abuse

 

for

 

parents

 

to

 

inflict

 

X

 

on

 

their

 

child

 

soon

 

after

 

birth,

 

then

 

it

 

must,

 

other

 

things

 

being

 

equal,

 

at

 

least

 

be

 

permissible

 

to

 

take

 

steps

 

to

 

prevent

 

one’s

 

child

 

having

 

that

 

condition.

48

 

 

 

46

 

(Parfit

 

1984).

 

47

 

(Glover

 

1984).

 

48

 

(Singer

 

2003).

 

 

18

background image

Julian

 

Savulescu

 

has

 

argued

 

for

 

a

 

principle

 

of

 

Procreative

 

Beneficence,

 

according

 

to

 

which

 

prospective

 

parents

 

should

 

select

 

the

 

child,

 

of

 

the

 

possible

 

children

 

they

 

could

 

have,

 

who

 

would

 

have

 

the

 

best

 

life,

 

based

 

on

 

the

 

relevant,

 

available

 

information

 

(where

 

the

 

“shouldâ€

 

is

 

meant

 

to

 

indicate

 

that

 

persuasion

 

is

 

justified,

 

but

 

not

 

coercion).

49

 

This

 

principle

 

does

 

not

 

presuppose

 

that

 

all

 

lives

 

can

 

be

 

placed

 

in

 

a

 

definite

 

ranking

 

with

 

respect

 

to

 

their

 

well

â€

being,

 

only

 

that

 

pair

â€

wise

 

comparisons

 

are

 

possible

 

in

 

at

 

least

 

some

 

cases.

 

For

 

instance,

 

if

 

a

 

couple

 

is

 

having

 

IVF

 

and

 

must

 

select

 

one

 

of

 

two

 

embryos

 

which

 

are

 

genetically

 

identical

 

except

 

that

 

one

 

of

 

them

 

has

 

one

 

defective

 

gene

 

that

 

predisposes

 

to

 

asthma,

 

then

 

Procreative

 

Beneficence

 

suggests

 

they

 

ought

 

to

 

choose

 

the

 

healthy

 

embryo

 

for

 

implantation.

 

 

In

 

From

 

Chance

 

to

 

Choice

 

(2000),

 

Allen

 

Buchanan,

 

Dan

 

W.

 

Brock,

 

Norman

 

Daniels,

 

and

 

Daniel

 

Wikler,

 

examined

 

how

 

advances

 

in

 

genetic

 

engineering

 

should

 

affect

 

our

 

understanding

 

of

 

distributive

 

justice,

 

equal

 

opportunity,

 

our

 

rights

 

and

 

obligations

 

as

 

parents,

 

the

 

meaning

 

of

 

disability,

 

and

 

the

 

concept

 

of

 

human

 

nature

 

in

 

ethical

 

theory

 

and

 

practice.

50

 

They

 

developed

 

a

 

framework

 

inspired

 

by

 

John

 

Rawls’s

 

work

 

in

 

an

 

attempt

 

to

 

answer

 

some

 

of

 

these

 

questions.

 

 

Greg

 

Stock,

 

John

 

Harris,

 

Gregory

 

Pence,

 

and

 

Eric

 

Juengst,

 

among

 

others,

 

have

 

also

 

discussed

 

the

 

ethics

 

of

 

genetic

 

engineering

 

from

 

a

 

broadly

 

transhumanist

 

perspective.

51

 

Mark

 

Walker

 

has

 

argued

 

from

 

a

 

perfectionist

 

standpoint

 

that

 

we

 

have

 

a

 

duty

 

to

 

use

 

technology

 

to

 

improve

 

ourselves.

 

Walker

 

has

 

also

 

argued

 

that

 

one

 

reason

 

to

 

pursue

 

cognitive

 

enhancements

 

is

 

that

 

it

 

could

 

help

 

us

 

solve

 

philosophical

 

problems.

52

 

Nick

 

Bostrom

 

and

 

several

 

others

 

have

 

drawn

 

attention

 

to

 

the

 

distinction

 

between

 

enhancements

 

that

 

offer

 

only

 

positional

 

advantages

 

(e.g.

 

an

 

increase

 

in

 

height),

 

which

 

are

 

only

 

advantages

 

insofar

 

as

 

others

 

lack

 

them,

 

and

 

enhancements

 

that

 

provide

 

either

 

intrinsic

 

benefits

 

or

 

net

 

positive

 

externalities

 

(such

 

as

 

a

 

better

 

immune

 

system

 

or

 

improvement

 

of

 

cognitive

 

functioning).

 

We

 

ought

 

to

 

promote

 

enhancements

 

of

 

the

 

second

 

kind,

 

but

 

not

 

enhancements

 

that

 

are

 

merely

 

positional.

53

 

 

Bostrom

 

has

 

suggested

 

that

 

we

 

have

 

a

 

reason

 

to

 

develop

 

means

 

to

 

explore

 

the

 

“larger

 

space

 

of

 

possible

 

modes

 

of

 

beingâ€

 

that

 

is

 

currently

 

inaccessible

 

to

 

us

 

because

 

of

 

our

 

biological

 

limitations,

 

on

 

the

 

ground

 

that

 

we

 

might

 

find

 

that

 

it

 

contains

 

extremely

 

worthwhile

 

modes

 

of

 

being

 

–

 

ways

 

of

 

living,

 

thinking,

 

feeling,

 

and

 

relating.

54

 

Along

 

with

 

many

 

other

 

                                                        

49

 

(Savulescu

 

2001).

 

50

 

(Buchanan

 

et

 

al.

 

2002).

 

51

 

E.g.

 

(Stock

 

2002;

 

Harris

 

1992;

 

Pence

 

1998;

 

Parens

 

1998).

 

52

 

(Walker

 

2002).

 

53

 

(Bostrom

 

2003).

 

54

 

(Bostrom

 

2004).

 

 

19

background image

transhumanist

 

writers,

 

Bostrom

 

has

 

argued

 

for

 

the

 

moral

 

urgency

 

of

 

developing

 

means

 

to

 

slow

 

or

 

reverse

 

the

 

aging

 

process.

55

 

He

 

has

 

also

 

proposed

 

a

 

broader

 

conception

 

of

 

human

 

dignity

 

which

 

can

 

accommodate

 

“posthuman

 

dignityâ€.

56

 

A

 

recent

 

joint

 

paper

 

by

 

Bostrom

 

and

 

Toby

 

Ord

 

proposes

 

a

 

heuristic

 

for

 

eliminating

 

“status

 

quoâ€

 

bias

 

in

 

bioethics,

 

a

 

bias

 

which,

 

they

 

claim,

 

afflicts

 

many

 

of

 

our

 

moral

 

intuitions.

57

 

 

Eliezer

 

Yudkowsky

 

(an

 

independent

 

scholar)

 

has

 

probed

 

the

 

ethics

 

of

 

superintelligence

 

and

 

has

 

tried

 

to

 

develop

 

a

 

theory

 

of

 

how

 

to

 

program

 

a

 

human

â€

friendly

 

AI,

 

a

 

challenge

 

that

 

could

 

take

 

on

 

life

â€

and

â€

death

 

significance

 

once

 

we

 

become

 

capable

 

of

 

creating

 

such

 

a

 

machine.

 

Yudkowsky

 

argues

 

that

 

simple

 

rule

â€

based

 

injunctions

 

(such

 

as

 

Isaac

 

Asimov’s

 

“three

 

laws

 

of

 

roboticsâ€)

 

would

 

produce

 

deadly

 

unintended

 

consequences.

 

He

 

conceives

 

of

 

a

 

superintelligence

 

as

 

an

 

enormously

 

powerful

 

optimization

 

process,

 

and

 

the

 

central

 

task

 

is

 

to

 

specify

 

the

 

mental

 

architecture

 

and

 

goal

â€

structure

 

of

 

the

 

AI

 

in

 

such

 

a

 

way

 

that

 

it

 

realizes

 

desirable

 

outcomes.

 

Rather

 

than

 

creating

 

a

 

list

 

of

 

specific

 

goals,

 

Yudkowsky

 

argues

 

that

 

we

 

need

 

to

 

take

 

a

 

more

 

indirect

 

approach

 

and

 

choose

 

the

 

AI’s

 

initial

 

conditions

 

so

 

that

 

it

 

would

 

use

 

its

 

superior

 

intellectual

 

powers

 

to

 

derive

 

the

 

specific

 

goals

 

and

 

extrapolate

 

our

 

decisions

 

if

 

we

 

were

 

better

 

calibrated,

 

better

 

informed,

 

and

 

better

 

able

 

to

 

reflect

 

on

 

the

 

forces

 

influencing

 

our

 

decisions.

 

Yudkowsky

 

also

 

wishes

 

to

 

specify

 

an

 

AI

 

that

 

would

 

use

 

its

 

initial

 

rules

 

for

 

extrapolation

 

to

 

extrapolate

 

smarter

 

human

 

decisions

 

about

 

extrapolation

 

rules;

 

in

 

effect,

 

a

 

set

 

of

 

initial

 

rules

 

for

 

extrapolation

 

would

 

“renormalizeâ€

 

themselves.

58

 

 

Aside

 

from

 

normative

 

questions,

 

there

 

are

 

also

 

positive

 

questions

 

to

 

be

 

asked,

 

about

 

the

 

nature

 

and

 

timing

 

of

 

transforming

 

technologies

 

and

 

their

 

consequences.

 

Hans

 

Moravec’s

 

1989

â€

book

 

Mind

 

Children

 

explored

 

the

 

ramifications

 

of

 

possible

 

future

 

advances

 

in

 

robotics

 

and

 

uploading.

59

 

A

 

later

 

Moravec

 

book,

 

Robot

 

(1999),

 

and

 

Ray

 

Kurzweil’s

 

best

â€

selling

 

Age

 

of

 

Spiritual

 

Machines

 

(1999)

 

introduced

 

these

 

ideas

 

to

 

a

 

wider

 

audience.

60,61

 

As

 

we

 

have

 

seen,

 

Eric

 

Drexler

 

was

 

trying

 

to

 

anticipate

 

the

 

consequences

 

of

 

molecular

 

nanotechnology

 

back

 

in

 

the

 

80s,

 

an

 

endeavor

 

in

 

which

 

he

 

has

 

since

 

been

 

joined

 

by

 

several

 

other

 

researchers

 

such

 

as

 

Robert

 

Freitas,

 

who

 

has

 

studied

 

potential

 

medical

 

application

 

of

 

nanotechnology

 

in

 

great

 

detail,

 

and

 

Ralph

 

Merkle

 

who

 

has

 

collaborated

 

with

 

Freitas

 

to

 

study

 

the

 

kinematics

 

of

 

self

â€

replicating

 

systems

 

and

 

the

 

technical

 

steps

 

towards

 

crude

 

molecular

 

assemblers.

62

 

All

 

these

 

                                                        

55

 

(Bostrom

 

2005).

 

56

 

(Bostrom

 

2005).

 

57

 

(Bostrom

 

and

 

Ord

 

2005).

 

58

 

(Yudkowsky

 

2004).

 

59

 

(Moravec

 

1989).

 

60

 

(Moravec

 

1999).

 

61

 

(Kurzweil

 

1999).

 

62

 

(Freitas

 

and

 

Merkle

 

2005).

 

 

20

background image

authors

 

recognize

 

that

 

technologies

 

as

 

potent

 

as

 

superintelligence

 

or

 

molecular

 

nanotechnology

 

are

 

not

 

without

 

serious

 

risks

 

of

 

accidents

 

or

 

deliberate

 

misuse.

 

 

Bostrom

 

(2002)

 

introduced

 

the

 

concept

 

of

 

an

 

“existential

 

riskâ€,

 

defined

 

as

 

“one

 

where

 

an

 

adverse

 

outcome

 

would

 

either

 

annihilate

 

Earth

â€

originating

 

intelligent

 

life

 

or

 

permanently

 

and

 

drastically

 

curtail

 

its

 

potentialâ€,

 

and

 

created

 

a

 

catalogue

 

of

 

what

 

he

 

saw

 

as

 

the

 

most

 

probable

 

existential

 

risks.

63

 

Both

 

nanotechnology

â€Â 

and

 

superintelligence

â€

related

 

risks

 

attain

 

high

 

ranks

 

on

 

that

 

list.

 

In

 

a

 

much

â€

discussed

 

popular

 

article,

 

“Why

 

the

 

Future

 

Doesn’t

 

Need

 

Usâ€

 

(2000),

 

Bill

 

Joy

 

argued

 

that

 

we

 

ought

 

to

 

relinquish

 

developments

 

in

 

AI,

 

nanotechnology,

 

and

 

genetics

 

because

 

of

 

the

 

risks

 

that

 

will

 

eventually

 

emerge

 

from

 

these

 

disciplines.

64

 

Several

 

people,

 

reacting

 

to

 

Joy,

 

argued

 

against

 

such

 

bans

 

on

 

grounds

 

that

 

they

 

are

 

unrealistic,

 

would

 

deprive

 

us

 

of

 

great

 

benefits,

 

and

 

might

 

increase

 

rather

 

than

 

decrease

 

risk

 

if

 

development

 

were

 

driven

 

underground

 

or

 

to

 

less

 

hesitant

 

regions

 

of

 

the

 

world.

 

John

 

Leslie,

 

Martin

 

Rees,

 

and

 

Richard

 

Posner

 

have

 

also

 

investigated

 

threats

 

to

 

human

 

survival

 

in

 

the

 

21

st

 

century

 

–

 

all

 

of

 

them

 

have

 

rated

 

the

 

risk

 

as

 

highly

 

significant.

65

 

 

Robin

 

Hanson

 

has

 

analyzed

 

several

 

topics

 

of

 

relevance

 

to

 

human

 

transformation,

 

including

 

the

 

consequences

 

of

 

uploading

 

in

 

an

 

unregulated

 

economy,

 

the

 

social

â€

signaling

 

function

 

of

 

beliefs,

 

the

 

sources

 

and

 

epistemological

 

status

 

of

 

disagreements

 

of

 

opinion,

 

the

 

dynamics

 

of

 

a

 

space

 

colonization

 

race,

 

and

 

information

 

markets

 

as

 

a

 

system

 

for

 

aggregating

 

information

 

and

 

guiding

 

policy.

66

 

Related

 

to

 

Hanson’s

 

work

 

on

 

upload

 

competition

 

and

 

colonization

 

races,

 

Bostrom

 

has

 

explored

 

how

 

dystopian

 

outcomes

 

could

 

result

 

in

 

some

 

future

 

evolutionary

 

scenarios.

67

 

Drawing

 

on

 

his

 

earlier

 

work

 

on

 

observation

 

selection

 

effects,

 

he

 

also

 

formulated

 

the

 

Simulation

 

argument,

 

which

 

purports

 

to

 

show

 

that

 

it

 

follows

 

from

 

some

 

fairly

 

weak

 

assumptions

 

that

 

 

at

 

least

 

one

 

of

 

the

 

following

 

propositions

 

is

 

true:

 

(1)

 

the

 

human

 

species

 

is

 

very

 

likely

 

to

 

go

 

extinct

 

before

 

reaching

 

a

 

“posthumanâ€

 

stage;

 

(2)

 

any

 

posthuman

 

civilization

 

is

 

extremely

 

unlikely

 

to

 

run

 

a

 

significant

 

number

 

of

 

simulations

 

of

 

their

 

evolutionary

 

history

 

(or

 

variations

 

thereof);

 

(3)

 

we

 

are

 

almost

 

certainly

 

living

 

in

 

a

 

computer

 

simulation.

 

It

 

follows

 

that

 

the

 

belief

 

that

 

there

 

is

 

a

 

significant

 

chance

 

that

 

we

 

will

 

one

 

day

 

become

 

posthumans

 

who

 

run

 

ancestor

â€

simulations

 

is

 

false,

 

unless

 

we

 

are

 

currently

 

living

 

in

 

a

 

simulation.

68

 

                                                        

63

 

(Bostrom

 

2002).

 

64

 

(Joy

 

2000).

 

65

 

(Leslie

 

1996;

 

Rees

 

2003;

 

Posner

 

2004).

 

66

 

E.g.

 

(Hanson

 

1994,

 

1995,

 

1998).

 

67

 

(Bostrom

 

2005).

 

68

 

(Bostrom

 

2003).

 

 

21

background image

 

We

 

do

 

not

 

know

 

what

 

will

 

happen,

 

but

 

several

 

subtle

 

constraints

 

enable

 

us

 

to

 

narrow

 

down

 

the

 

range

 

of

 

tenable

 

views

 

about

 

humanity’s

 

future

 

and

 

our

 

place

 

in

 

the

 

universe.

 

These

 

constraints

 

derive

 

from

 

a

 

variety

 

of

 

sources,

 

including

 

analysis

 

of

 

the

 

capacities

 

of

 

possible

 

technologies

 

based

 

on

 

physical

 

or

 

chemical

 

simulations;

 

economic

 

analysis;

 

evolution

 

theory;

 

probability

 

theory;

 

game

 

theory

 

and

 

strategic

 

analysis;

 

and

 

cosmology.

 

Partly

 

because

 

of

 

the

 

interdisciplinary

 

and

 

sometimes

 

technical

 

nature

 

of

 

these

 

considerations,

 

they

 

are

 

not

 

widely

 

understood.

 

Yet

 

any

 

serious

 

attempt

 

to

 

grapple

 

with

 

the

 

long

â€

term

 

implications

 

of

 

technological

 

development

 

should

 

take

 

them

 

into

 

account.

 

 

 

6.

 

21

st

 

century

 

biopolitics:

 

the

 

transhumanist

â€

bioconservative

 

dimension

 

James

 

Hughes

 

has

 

argued

 

that

 

biopolitics

 

is

 

emerging

 

as

 

a

 

fundamental

 

new

 

dimension

 

of

 

political

 

opinion.

 

In

 

Hughes’

 

model,

 

biopolitics

 

joins

 

with

 

the

 

more

 

familiar

 

dimensions

 

of

 

cultural

 

and

 

economic

 

politics,

 

to

 

form

 

a

 

three

â€

dimensional

 

opinion

â€

space.

 

We

 

have

 

already

 

seen

 

that

 

in

 

the

 

early

 

90s,

 

the

 

extropians

 

combined

 

liberal

 

cultural

 

politics

 

and

 

laissez

â€

faire

 

laissez

â€

fair

 

economic

 

politics

 

with

 

transhumanist

 

biopolitics.

 

In

 

Citizen

 

Cyborg

 

(2004),

 

Hughes

 

sets

 

forward

 

what

 

he

 

terms

 

“democratic

 

transhumanism,â€

 

which

 

mates

 

transhumanist

 

biopolitics

 

with

 

social

 

democratic

 

economic

 

politics

 

and

 

liberal

 

cultural

 

politics.

69

 

He

 

argues

 

that

 

we

 

will

 

achieve

 

the

 

best

 

posthuman

 

future

 

when

 

we

 

ensure

 

that

 

technologies

 

are

 

safe,

 

make

 

them

 

available

 

to

 

everyone,

 

and

 

respect

 

the

 

right

 

of

 

individuals

 

to

 

control

 

their

 

own

 

bodies.

 

The

 

key

 

difference

 

between

 

extropian

 

transhumanism

 

and

 

democratic

 

transhumanism

 

is

 

that

 

the

 

latter

 

accords

 

a

 

much

 

bigger

 

role

 

for

 

government

 

in

 

regulating

 

new

 

technologies

 

for

 

safety

 

and

 

ensuring

 

that

 

the

 

benefits

 

will

 

be

 

available

 

to

 

all,

 

not

 

just

 

a

 

wealthy

 

or

 

tech

â€

savvy

 

elite.

 

 

In

 

principle,

 

transhumanism

 

can

 

be

 

combined

 

with

 

a

 

wide

 

range

 

of

 

political

 

and

 

cultural

 

views,

 

and

 

many

 

such

 

combinations

 

are

 

indeed

 

represented,

 

e.g.

 

within

 

the

 

membership

 

of

 

the

 

World

 

Transhumanist

 

Association.

 

One

 

combination

 

that

 

is

 

not

 

often

 

found

 

is

 

the

 

coupling

 

of

 

transhumanism

 

to

 

a

 

culture

â€

conservative

 

outlook.

 

Whether

 

this

 

is

 

because

 

of

 

an

 

irresolvable

 

tension

 

between

 

the

 

transformative

 

agenda

 

of

 

transhumanism

 

and

 

the

 

cultural

 

conservative’s

 

preference

 

for

 

traditional

 

arrangements

 

is

 

not

 

clear.

 

It

 

could

 

instead

 

be

 

because

 

nobody

 

has

 

yet

 

seriously

 

attempted

 

to

 

develop

 

such

 

a

 

position.

 

It

 

is

 

possible

 

to

 

imagine

 

how

 

new

 

technologies

 

could

 

be

 

used

 

to

 

reinforce

 

some

 

culture

â€

conservative

 

values.

 

For

 

instance,

 

a

 

pharmaceutical

 

that

 

facilitated

 

long

â€

term

 

pair

 

bonding

 

could

 

help

 

protect

 

the

 

traditional

 

family.

 

Developing

 

ways

 

of

 

using

 

our

 

growing

 

technological

 

powers

 

to

 

help

 

                                                        

69

 

(Hughes

 

2004).

 

 

22

background image

people

 

realize

 

widely

 

held

 

cultural

 

or

 

spiritual

 

values

 

in

 

their

 

lives

 

would

 

seem

 

a

 

worthwhile

 

undertaking.

 

 

This

 

is

 

not,

 

however,

 

the

 

route

 

for

 

which

 

cultural

 

conservatives

 

have

 

so

 

far

 

opted.

 

Instead,

 

they

 

have

 

gravitated

 

towards

 

transhumanism’s

 

opposite,

 

bioconservatism,

 

which

 

opposes

 

the

 

use

 

of

 

technology

 

to

 

expand

 

human

 

capacities

 

or

 

to

 

modify

 

aspects

 

of

 

our

 

biological

 

nature.

 

People

 

drawn

 

to

 

bioconservatism

 

come

 

from

 

groups

 

that

 

traditionally

 

have

 

had

 

little

 

in

 

common.

 

Right

â€

wing

 

religious

 

conservatives

 

and

 

left

â€

wing

 

environmentalists

 

and

 

anti

â€

globalists

 

have

 

found

 

common

 

causes,

 

for

 

example

 

in

 

their

 

opposition

 

to

 

the

 

genetic

 

modification

 

of

 

humans.

 

 

The

 

different

 

strands

 

of

 

contemporary

 

bioconservatism

 

can

 

be

 

traced

 

to

 

a

 

multifarious

 

set

 

of

 

origins:

 

ancient

 

notions

 

of

 

taboo;

 

the

 

Greek

 

concept

 

of

 

hubris;

 

the

 

Romanticist

 

view

 

of

 

nature;

 

certain

 

religious

 

(anti

â€

humanistic)

 

interpretations

 

of

 

the

 

concept

 

of

 

human

 

dignity

 

and

 

of

 

a

 

God

â€

given

 

natural

 

order;

 

the

 

Luddite

 

workers’

 

revolt

 

against

 

industrialization;

 

Karl

 

Marx’s

 

analysis

 

of

 

technology

 

under

 

capitalism;

 

various

 

Continental

 

philosopher’s

 

critiques

 

of

 

technology,

 

technocracy,

 

and

 

the

 

rationalistic

 

mindset

 

that

 

accompanies

 

modern

 

technoscience;

 

foes

 

of

 

the

 

military

â€

industrial

 

complex

 

and

 

multinational

 

corporations;

 

and

 

objectors

 

to

 

the

 

consumerist

 

rat

â€

race.

 

The

 

proposed

 

remedies

 

have

 

ranged

 

from

 

machine

â€

smashing

 

(the

 

original

 

Luddites),

 

to

 

communist

 

revolution

 

(Marx),

 

to

 

buying

 

“organicâ€,

 

to

 

yoga

 

(José

 

Ortega

 

y

 

Gasset),

 

–

 

but

 

nowadays

 

it

 

commonly

 

emanates

 

in

 

calls

 

for

 

national

 

or

 

international

 

bans

 

on

 

various

 

human

 

enhancement

 

technologies

 

(Fukuyama,

 

Annas,

 

etc.).

 

 

Feminist

 

writers

 

have

 

come

 

down

 

on

 

both

 

sides

 

of

 

the

 

debate.

 

Ecofeminists

 

have

 

suspected

 

biotechnology,

 

especially

 

its

 

use

 

to

 

reshape

 

bodies

 

or

 

control

 

reproduction,

 

of

 

being

 

an

 

extension

 

of

 

traditional

 

patriarchal

 

exploitation

 

of

 

women,

 

or,

 

alternatively,

 

have

 

seen

 

it

 

as

 

a

 

symptom

 

of

 

a

 

control

â€

obsessed,

 

unemphatic,

 

gadget

â€

fixated,

 

body

â€

loathing

 

mindset.

 

Some

 

have

 

offered

 

a

 

kind

 

of

 

psychoanalysis

 

of

 

transhumanism,

 

concluding

 

that

 

it

 

represents

 

an

 

embarrassing

 

rationalization

 

of

 

self

â€

centered

 

immaturity

 

and

 

social

 

failure.

 

But

 

others

 

have

 

welcomed

 

the

 

libratory

 

potential

 

of

 

biotechnology.

 

Shulamith

 

Firestone

 

argued

 

in

 

the

 

feminist

 

classic

 

The

 

Dialectic

 

of

 

Sex

 

(1971)

 

that

 

women

 

will

 

be

 

fully

 

liberated

 

only

 

when

 

technology

 

has

 

freed

 

them

 

from

 

having

 

to

 

incubate

 

children.

70

 

Cyberfeminist

 

Donna

 

Haraway

 

proclaims

 

that

 

she

 

would

 

“rather

 

be

 

a

 

cyborg

 

than

 

a

 

goddessâ€

 

and

 

argues

 

against

 

the

 

dualistic

 

view

 

that

 

associates

 

men

 

with

 

culture

 

and

 

technology

 

and

 

women

 

with

 

nature.

71

 

 

                                                        

70

 

(Firestone

 

1970).

 

71

 

(Haraway

 

1991).

 

 

23

background image

Perhaps

 

the

 

most

 

prominent

 

bioconservative

 

voice

 

today

 

is

 

that

 

of

 

Leon

 

Kass,

 

chairman

 

of

 

President

 

Bush’s

 

Council

 

on

 

Bioethics

 

[[Q:

 

still

 

extant?]]

.

 

Kass

 

acknowledges

 

an

 

intellectual

 

debt

 

to

 

three

 

other

 

distinguished

 

bioconservatives:

 

Protestant

 

theologian

 

Paul

 

Ramsey,

 

Christian

 

apologist

 

apologetic

 

C.

 

S.

 

Lewis,

 

and

 

German

â€

born

 

philosopher

â€

theologian

 

Hans

 

Jonas

 

(who

 

studied

 

under

 

Martin

 

Heidegger).

 

Kass’s

 

concerns

 

center

 

on

 

human

 

dignity

 

and

 

the

 

subtle

 

ways

 

in

 

which

 

our

 

attempts

 

to

 

assert

 

technological

 

mastery

 

over

 

human

 

nature

 

could

 

end

 

up

 

dehumanizing

 

us

 

by

 

undermining

 

various

 

traditional

 

“meaningsâ€

 

such

 

as

 

the

 

meaning

 

of

 

the

 

life

 

cycle,

 

the

 

meaning

 

of

 

sex,

 

the

 

meaning

 

of

 

eating,

 

and

 

the

 

meaning

 

of

 

work.

 

Kass

 

is

 

well

 

known

 

well

â€

known

 

for

 

his

 

advocacy

 

of

 

“the

 

wisdom

 

of

 

repugnanceâ€

 

(which

 

echoes

 

Hans

 

Jonas’s

 

“heuristics

 

of

 

fearâ€).

 

While

 

Kass

 

stresses

 

that

 

a

 

gut

 

feeling

 

of

 

revulsion

 

is

 

not

 

a

 

moral

 

argument,

 

he

 

nevertheless

 

insists

 

that

 

the

 

yuck

 

factor

 

merits

 

our

 

respectful

 

attention:

 

 

In

 

crucial

 

cases

 

…

 

repugnance

 

is

 

the

 

emotional

 

expression

 

of

 

deep

 

wisdom,

 

beyond

 

reason’s

 

power

 

to

 

fully

 

articulate

 

…

 

we

 

intuit

 

and

 

feel,

 

immediately

 

and

 

without

 

argument,

 

the

 

violation

 

of

 

things

 

we

 

rightfully

 

hold

 

dear

 

…

 

To

 

pollution

 

and

 

perversion,

 

the

 

fitting

 

response

 

can

 

only

 

be

 

horror

 

and

 

revulsion;

 

and

 

conversely,

 

generalized

 

horror

 

and

 

revulsion

 

are

 

prima

 

facie

 

evidence

 

of

 

foulness

 

and

 

violation.

 

Francis

 

Fukuyama,

 

another

 

prominent

 

bioconservative

 

and

 

member

 

of

 

the

 

President’s

 

Council,

 

has

 

recently

 

identified

 

transhumanism

 

as

 

“the

 

world’s

 

most

 

dangerous

 

ideaâ€.

 

For

 

Fukuyama,

 

however,

 

the

 

chief

 

concern

 

is

 

not

 

about

 

the

 

subtle

 

undermining

 

of

 

“meaningsâ€

 

but

 

the

 

prospect

 

of

 

violence

 

and

 

oppression.

 

He

 

argues

 

that

 

liberal

 

democracy

 

depends

 

on

 

the

 

fact

 

that

 

all

 

humans

 

share

 

an

 

undefined

 

“Factor

 

Xâ€,

 

which

 

grounds

 

their

 

equal

 

dignity

 

and

 

rights.

 

The

 

use

 

of

 

enhancing

 

technologies,

 

he

 

fears,

 

could

 

destroy

 

Factor

 

X.

 

Bioethicists

 

George

 

Annas,

 

Lori

 

Andrews,

 

and

 

Rosario

 

Isasi

 

have

 

proposed

 

legislation

 

to

 

make

 

inheritable

 

genetic

 

modification

 

in

 

humans

 

a

 

“crime

 

against

 

humanityâ€,

 

like

 

torture

 

and

 

genocide.

 

Their

 

rationale

 

is

 

similar

 

to

 

Fukuyama’s:

 

 

The

 

new

 

species,

 

or

 

“posthuman,â€

 

will

 

likely

 

view

 

the

 

old

 

“normalâ€

 

humans

 

as

 

inferior,

 

even

 

savages,

 

and

 

fit

 

for

 

slavery

 

or

 

slaughter.

 

The

 

normals,

 

on

 

the

 

other

 

hand,

 

may

 

see

 

the

 

posthumans

 

as

 

a

 

threat

 

and

 

if

 

they

 

can,

 

may

 

engage

 

in

 

a

 

                                                        

72

 

(Kass

 

2002).

 

73

 

(Kass

 

1997).

 

74

 

(Fukuyama

 

2004).

 

For

 

a

 

response,

 

see

 

(Bostrom

 

2004).

 

75

 

(Fukuyama

 

2002).

 

 

24

background image

preemptive

 

strike

 

by

 

killing

 

the

 

posthumans

 

before

 

they

 

themselves

 

are

 

killed

 

or

 

enslaved

 

by

 

them.

 

It

 

is

 

ultimately

 

this

 

predictable

 

potential

 

for

 

genocide

 

that

 

makes

 

species

â€

altering

 

experiments

 

potential

 

weapons

 

of

 

mass

 

destruction,

 

and

 

makes

 

the

 

unaccountable

 

genetic

 

engineer

 

a

 

potential

 

bioterrorist.

76

 

 

There

 

is

 

some

 

common

 

ground

 

between

 

Annas

 

et

 

al.

 

and

 

the

 

transhumanists:

 

they

 

agree

 

that

 

murder

 

and

 

enslavement,

 

whether

 

of

 

humans

 

by

 

posthumans

 

or

 

the

 

other

 

way

 

around,

 

would

 

be

 

a

 

moral

 

atrocity

 

and

 

a

 

crime.

 

Transhumanists

 

deny,

 

however,

 

that

 

this

 

is

 

a

 

likely

 

consequence

 

of

 

germ

â€

line

 

therapy

 

to

 

enhance

 

health,

 

memory,

 

longevity,

 

or

 

other

 

similar

 

traits

 

in

 

humans.

 

If

 

and

 

when

 

we

 

develop

 

the

 

capability

 

to

 

create

 

some

 

singular

 

entity

 

that

 

could

 

potentially

 

destroy

 

the

 

human

 

race,

 

such

 

as

 

a

 

superintelligent

 

machine,

 

then

 

we

 

could

 

indeed

 

regard

 

it

 

as

 

a

 

crime

 

against

 

humanity

 

to

 

proceed

 

without

 

a

 

thorough

 

risk

 

analysis

 

and

 

the

 

installation

 

of

 

adequate

 

safety

 

features.

 

As

 

we

 

saw

 

in

 

the

 

previous

 

section,

 

the

 

effort

 

to

 

understand

 

and

 

find

 

ways

 

to

 

reduce

 

existential

 

risks

 

has

 

been

 

a

 

central

 

preoccupation

 

for

 

some

 

transhumanists,

 

such

 

as

 

Eric

 

Drexler,

 

Nick

 

Bostrom,

 

and

 

Eliezer

 

Yudkowsky.

 

 

There

 

are

 

other

 

commonalities

 

between

 

bioconservatives

 

and

 

transhumanists.

 

Both

 

agree

 

that

 

we

 

face

 

a

 

realistic

 

prospect

 

that

 

technology

 

could

 

be

 

used

 

to

 

substantially

 

transform

 

the

 

human

 

condition

 

in

 

this

 

century.

 

Both

 

agree

 

that

 

this

 

imposes

 

an

 

obligation

 

on

 

the

 

current

 

generation

 

to

 

think

 

hard

 

about

 

the

 

practical

 

and

 

ethical

 

implications.

 

Both

 

are

 

concerned

 

with

 

medical

 

risks

 

of

 

side

â€

effects,

 

of

 

course,

 

although

 

bioconservatives

 

are

 

more

 

worried

 

that

 

the

 

technology

 

might

 

succeed

 

than

 

that

 

it

 

might

 

fail.

 

Both

 

camps

 

agree

 

that

 

technology

 

in

 

general

 

and

 

medicine

 

in

 

particular

 

have

 

a

 

legitimate

 

role

 

to

 

play,

 

although

 

bioconservatives

 

tend

 

to

 

oppose

 

many

 

uses

 

of

 

medicine

 

that

 

go

 

beyond

 

therapy

 

to

 

enhancement.

 

Both

 

sides

 

condemn

 

the

 

racist

 

and

 

coercive

 

state

â€

sponsored

 

eugenics

 

programs

 

of

 

the

 

20

th

 

twentieth

 

century.

 

Bioconservatives

 

draw

 

attention

 

to

 

the

 

possibility

 

that

 

subtle

 

human

 

values

 

could

 

be

 

get

 

eroded

 

by

 

technological

 

advances,

 

and

 

transhumanists

 

should

 

perhaps

 

learn

 

to

 

be

 

more

 

sensitive

 

to

 

these

 

concerns.

 

On

 

the

 

other

 

hand,

 

transhumanists

 

emphasize

 

the

 

enormous

 

potential

 

for

 

genuine

 

improvements

 

in

 

human

 

well

â€

being

 

and

 

human

 

flourishing

 

that

 

are

 

attainable

 

only

 

via

 

technological

 

transformation,

 

and

 

bioconservatives

 

could

 

try

 

to

 

be

 

more

 

appreciative

 

of

 

the

 

possibility

 

that

 

we

 

could

 

realize

 

great

 

values

 

by

 

venturing

 

beyond

 

our

 

current

 

biological

 

limitations.

77

 

 

                                                        

76

 

(Annas,

 

Andrews,

 

and

 

Isasi

 

2002).

 

77

 

I’m

 

grateful

 

to

 

Anders

 

Sandberg

 

and

 

Sara

 

Lippincott

 

for

 

comments.

 

 

25

background image

Appendix

 

The

 

Transhumanist

 

Declaration

 

(Version

 

of

 

March

 

2009)

 

 

(1)

 

Humanity

 

stands

 

to

 

be

 

profoundly

 

affected

 

by

 

science

 

and

 

technology

 

in

 

the

 

future.

  

We

 

envision

 

the

 

possibility

 

of

 

broadening

 

human

 

potential

 

by

 

overcoming

 

aging,

 

cognitive

 

shortcomings,

 

involuntary

 

suffering,

 

and

 

our

 

confinement

 

to

 

planet

 

Earth.

 

 

(2)

 

We

 

believe

 

that

 

humanity

ʹ

s

 

potential

 

is

 

still

 

mostly

 

unrealized.

  

There

 

are

 

possible

 

scenarios

 

that

 

lead

 

to

 

wonderful

 

and

 

exceedingly

 

worthwhile

 

enhanced

 

human

 

conditions.

 

 

(3)

 

We

 

recognize

 

that

 

humanity

 

faces

 

serious

 

risks,

 

especially

 

from

 

the

 

misuse

 

of

 

new

 

technologies.

  

There

 

are

 

possible

 

realistic

 

scenarios

 

that

 

lead

 

to

 

the

 

loss

 

of

 

most,

 

or

 

even

 

all,

 

of

 

what

 

we

 

hold

 

valuable.

   

Some

 

of

 

these

 

scenarios

 

are

 

drastic,

 

others

 

are

 

subtle.

  

Although

 

all

 

progress

 

is

 

change,

 

not

 

all

 

change

 

is

 

progress.

 

 

(4)

 

Research

 

effort

 

needs

 

to

 

be

 

invested

 

into

 

understanding

 

these

 

prospects.

  

We

 

need

 

to

 

carefully

 

deliberate

 

how

 

best

 

to

 

reduce

 

risks

 

and

 

expedite

 

beneficial

 

applications.

  

We

 

also

 

need

 

forums

 

where

 

people

 

can

 

constructively

 

discuss

 

what

 

should

 

be

 

done,

 

and

 

a

 

social

 

order

 

where

 

responsible

 

decisions

 

can

 

be

 

implemented.

 

 

(5)

 

Reduction

 

of

 

existential

 

risks,

 

and

 

development

 

of

 

means

 

for

 

the

 

preservation

 

of

 

life

 

and

 

health,

 

the

 

alleviation

 

of

 

grave

 

suffering,

 

and

 

the

 

improvement

 

of

 

human

 

foresight

 

and

 

wisdom

 

should

 

be

 

pursued

 

as

 

urgent

 

priorities,

 

and

 

heavily

 

funded.

 

 

(6)

 

Policymaking

 

ought

 

to

 

be

 

guided

 

by

 

responsible

 

and

 

inclusive

 

moral

 

vision,

 

taking

 

seriously

 

both

 

opportunities

 

and

 

risks,

 

respecting

 

autonomy

 

and

 

individual

 

rights,

 

and

 

showing

 

solidarity

 

with

 

and

 

concern

 

for

 

the

 

interests

 

and

 

dignity

 

of

 

all

 

people

 

around

 

the

 

globe.

  

We

 

must

 

also

 

consider

 

our

 

moral

 

responsibilities

 

towards

 

generations

 

that

 

will

 

exist

 

in

 

the

 

future.

 

 

(7)

 

We

 

advocate

 

the

 

well

â€

being

 

of

 

all

 

sentience,

 

including

 

humans,

 

non

â€

human

 

animals,

 

and

 

any

 

future

 

artificial

 

intellects,

 

modified

 

life

 

forms,

 

or

 

other

 

intelligences

 

to

 

which

 

technological

 

and

 

scientific

 

advance

 

may

 

give

 

rise.

 

 

(8)

 

We

 

favor

 

allowing

 

individuals

 

wide

 

personal

 

choice

 

over

 

how

 

they

 

enable

 

their

 

lives.

  

This

 

includes

 

use

 

of

 

techniques

 

that

 

may

 

be

 

developed

 

to

 

assist

 

memory,

 

concentration,

 

and

 

mental

 

energy;

 

life

 

extension

 

therapies;

 

reproductive

 

choice

 

technologies;

 

cryonics

 

 

26

background image

procedures;

 

and

 

many

 

other

 

possible

 

human

 

modification

 

and

 

enhancement

 

technologies.

 

  

 

References

 

Annas,

 

G.,

 

L.

 

Andrews,

 

and

 

R.

 

Isasi

 

(2002),

 ʺ

Protecting

 

the

 

Endangered

 

Human:

 

Toward

 

an

 

International

 

Treaty

 

Prohibiting

 

Cloning

 

and

 

Inheritable

 

Alterations

ʺ

,

 

American

 

Journal

 

of

 

Law

 

and

 

Medicine

 

28

 

(2&3):151

â€

178.

 

Bacon,

 

F.

 

(1620),

 

Novum

 

Organum

.

 

Translated

 

by

 

R.

 

L.

 

Ellis

 

and

 

J.

 

Spedding.

 

Robertson,

 

J.

 

ed,

 

The

 

Philosophical

 

Woeks

 

of

 

Francis

 

Bacon,

 

1905

.

 

London:

 

Routledge.

 

Bernal,

 

J.

 

D.

 

(1969),

 

The

 

world,

 

the

 

flesh

 

&

 

the

 

devil;

 

an

 

enquiry

 

into

 

the

 

future

 

of

 

the

 

three

 

enemies

 

of

 

the

 

rational

 

soul

.

 

Bloomington:

 

Indiana

 

University

 

Press.

 

Bostrom,

 

N.

 

(1998),

 ʺ

How

 

Long

 

Before

 

Superintelligence?

ʺ 

International

 

Journal

 

of

 

Futures

 

Studies

 

2.

 

———

 

(2002),

 ʺ

Existential

 

Risks:

 

Analyzing

 

Human

 

Extinction

 

Scenarios

 

and

 

Related

 

Hazards

ʺ

,

 

Journal

 

of

 

Evolution

 

and

 

Technology

 

9.

 

———

 

(2002),

 ʺ

When

 

Machines

 

Outsmart

 

Humans

ʺ

,

 

Futures

 

35

 

(7):759

â€

764.

 

———

 

(2003),

 ʺ

Are

 

You

 

Living

 

in

 

a

 

Computer

 

Simulation?

ʺ 

Philosophical

 

Quarterly

 

53

 

(211):243

â€

255.

 

———

 

(2003),

 ʺ

Human

 

Genetic

 

Enhancements:

 

A

 

Transhumanist

 

Perspective

ʺ

,

 

Journal

 

of

 

Value

 

Inquiry

 

37

 

(4):493

â€

506.

 

———

 

The

 

Transhumanist

 

FAQ:

 

v

 

2.1

.

 

World

 

Transhumanist

 

Association

 

2003.

 

http://transhumanism.org/index.php/WTA/faq/

.

 

———

 

(2004),

 ʺ

Transhumanism

 â€Â 

The

 

World

ʹ

s

 

Most

 

Dangerous

 

Idea?

ʺ 

Betterhumans

 

10/19/2004.

 

———

 

(2004),

 ʺ

Transhumanist

 

Values

ʺ

,

 

in

 

Fredrick

 

Adams

 

(ed.),

 

Ethical

 

Issues

 

for

 

the

 

21st

 

Century

:

 

Philosophical

 

Documentation

 

Center

 

Press.

 

———

 

(2005),

 ʺ

The

 

Fable

 

of

 

the

 

Dragon

â€

Tyrant

ʺ

,

 

Journal

 

of

 

Medical

 

Ethics

 

31

 

(5):273

â€

277.

 

———

 

(2005),

 ʺ

The

 

Future

 

of

 

Human

 

Evolution

ʺ

,

 

in

 

Charles

 

Tandy

 

(ed.),

 

Death

 

and

 

Anti

â€

Death

:

 

Ria

 

University

 

Press.

 

———

 

(2005),

 ʺ

In

 

Defence

 

of

 

Posthuman

 

Dignity

ʺ

,

 

Bioethics

 

forthcoming.

 

Bostrom,

 

N.,

 

and

 

T.

 

Ord

 

(2005),

 ʺ

Status

 

Quo

 

Bias

 

in

 

Bioethics:

 

The

 

Case

 

for

 

Cognitive

 

Enhancement

ʺ

,

 

in

 

Nick

 

Bostrom

 

and

 

Julian

 

Savulescu

 

(eds.),

 

Improving

 

Humans

,

 

Oxford:

 

Oxford

 

University

 

Press.

 

Buchanan,

 

A.,

 

D.

 

W.

 

Brock,

 

N.

 

Daniels,

 

and

 

D.

 

Wikler

 

(2002),

 

From

 

Chance

 

to

 

Choice:

 

Genetics

 

and

 

Justice

:

 

Cambridge

 

University

 

Press.

 

Capek,

 

K.

 

(2004),

 

R.U.R.

 

(Rossum

ʹ

s

 

universal

 

robots)

,

 

Penguin

 

classics

.

 

London:

 

Penguin

 

Books.

 

Condorcet,

 

J.

â€

A.

â€

N.

 

d.

 

C.

 

(1979),

 

Sketch

 

for

 

a

 

historical

 

picture

 

of

 

the

 

progress

 

of

 

the

 

human

 

mind

.

 

Westport,

 

Conn.:

 

Greenwood

 

Press.

 

 

27

background image

Darwin,

 

C.

 

(2003),

 

The

 

origin

 

of

 

the

 

species

,

 

Barnes

 

&

 

noble

 

classics

.

 

New

 

York,

 

NY:

 

Fine

 

Creative

 

Media.

 

Drexler,

 

E.,

 

and

 

R.

 

Smalley

 

(1993),

 ʺ

Nanotechnology:

 

Drexler

 

and

 

Smalley

 

make

 

the

 

case

 

for

 

and

 

against

 ʹ

molecular

 

assemblers

ʹʺ

,

 

Chemical

 

&

 

Engineering

 

News

 

81

 

(48):37

â€

42.

 

Drexler,

 

K.

 

E.

 

(1985),

 

Engines

 

of

 

Creation:

 

The

 

Coming

 

Era

 

of

 

Nanotechnology

.

 

London:

 

Forth

 

Estate.

 

———

 

(1992),

 

Nanosystems:

 

Molecular

 

Machinery,

 

Manufacturing,

 

and

 

Computation

.

 

New

 

York:

 

John

 

Wiley

 

&

 

Sons,

 

Inc.

 

Esfandiary,

 

F.

 

M.

 

(1970),

 

Optimism

 

one;

 

the

 

emerging

 

radicalism

.

 

New

 

York:

 

Norton.

 

Ettinger,

 

R.

 

(1964),

 

The

 

prospect

 

of

 

immortality

.

 

New

 

York:

 

Doubleday.

 

Ettinger,

 

R.

 

C.

 

W.

 

(1972),

 

Man

 

into

 

superman;

 

the

 

startling

 

potential

 

of

 

human

 

evolution

â€â€

and

 

how

 

to

 

be

 

part

 

of

 

it

.

 

New

 

York:

 

St.

 

Martin

ʹ

s

 

Press.

 

Feynman,

 

R.

 

(1960),

 ʺ

There

 

is

 

Plenty

 

of

 

Room

 

at

 

the

 

Bottom

ʺ

,

 

Engineering

 

and

 

Science

 

Feb.

 

Firestone,

 

S.

 

(1970),

 

The

 

dialectic

 

of

 

sex;

 

the

 

case

 

for

 

feminist

 

revolution

.

 

New

 

York,:

 

Morrow.

 

FM

â€

2030

 

(1989),

 

Are

 

you

 

a

 

transhuman?:

 

monitoring

 

and

 

stimulating

 

your

 

personal

 

rate

 

of

 

growth

 

in

 

a

 

rapidly

 

changing

 

world

.

 

New

 

York,

 

NY:

 

Warner

 

Books.

 

Franklin,

 

B.,

 

et

 

al.

 

(1956),

 

Mr.

 

Franklin:

 

a

 

selection

 

from

 

his

 

personal

 

letters

.

 

New

 

Haven:

 

Yale

 

University

 

Press.

 

Freitas,

 

R.,

 

and

 

R.

 

Merkle

 

(2005),

 

Diamond

 

Surfaces

 

and

 

Diamond

 

Mechanosynthesis

.

 

Georgetown,

 

TX:

 

Landes

 

Bioscience.

 

Fukuyama,

 

F.

 

(2002),

 

Our

 

Posthuman

 

Future:

 

Consequences

 

of

 

the

 

Biotechnology

 

Revolution

:

 

Farrar,

 

Straus

 

and

 

Giroux.

 

———

 

(2004),

 ʺ

Transhumanism

ʺ

,

 

Foreign

 

Affairs

 

September/October.

 

Glover,

 

J.

 

(1984),

 

What

 

Sort

 

of

 

People

 

Should

 

There

 

Be?

:

 

Pelican.

 

Good,

 

I.

 

J.

 

(1965),

 ʺ

Speculations

 

Concerning

 

the

 

First

 

Ultraintelligent

 

Machine

ʺ

,

 

Advances

 

in

 

Computers

 

6:31

â€

88.

 

Haldane,

 

J.

 

B.

 

S.

 

(1924),

 

Daedalus;

 

or,

 

Science

 

and

 

the

 

future

.

 

London,:

 

K.

 

Paul,

 

Trench,

 

Trubner

 

&

 

co.,

 

ltd.

 

Hanson,

 

R.

 

(1994),

 ʺ

What

 

If

 

Uploads

 

Come

 

First:

 

The

 

Crack

 

of

 

a

 

Future

 

Dawn

ʺ

,

 

Extropy

 

6

 

(2).

 

———

 

(1995),

 ʺ

Could

 

Gambling

 

Save

 

Science?

 

Encouraging

 

an

 

Honest

 

Consensus

ʺ

,

 

Social

 

Epistemology

 

9:1:3

â€

33.

 

———

 

Burning

 

the

 

Cosmic

 

Commons:

 

Evolutionary

 

Strategies

 

for

 

Interstellar

 

Colonization

 

1998.

 

http://hanson.gmu.edu/filluniv.pdf

.

 

Haraway,

 

D.

 

(1991),

 ʺ

A

 

Cyborg

 

Manifesto:

 

Science,

 

Technology,

 

and

 

Socialist

â€

Feminism

 

in

 

the

 

Late

 

Twentieth

 

Century

ʺ

,

 

in,

 

Simians,

 

Cyborgs

 

and

 

Women:

 

The

 

Reinvention

 

of

 

Nature

,

 

New

 

York:

 

Routledge,

 

149

â€

181.

 

Harris,

 

J.

 

(1992),

 

Wonderwoman

 

and

 

Superman:

 

the

 

ethics

 

of

 

human

 

biotechnology

,

 

Studies

 

in

 

bioethics

.

 

Oxford:

 

Oxford

 

University

 

Press.

 

 

28

background image

Hughes,

 

J.

 

(2004),

 

Citizen

 

Cyborg:

 

why

 

democratic

 

societies

 

must

 

respond

 

to

 

the

 

redesigned

 

human

 

of

 

the

 

future

.

 

Cambridge,

 

MA:

 

Westview

 

Press.

 

Huxley,

 

A.

 

(1932),

 

Brave

 

New

 

World

.

 

London:

 

Chatto

 

&

 

Windus.

 

Huxley,

 

J.

 

(1927),

 

Religion

 

without

 

revelation

.

 

London:

 

E.

 

Benn.

 

Jonsen,

 

A.

 

R.

 

(1998),

 

The

 

birth

 

of

 

bioethics

.

 

New

 

York:

 

Oxford

 

University

 

Press.

 

Joy,

 

B.

 

(2000),

 ʺ

Why

 

the

 

future

 

doesn

ʹ

t

 

need

 

us

ʺ

,

 

Wired

 

8.04.

 

Kant,

 

I.

 

(1986),

 

Philosophical

 

writings

,

 

The

 

German

 

library;

 

v.

 

13

.

 

New

 

York:

 

Continuum.

 

Kass,

 

L.

 

(1997),

 ʺ

The

 

Wisdom

 

of

 

Repugnance

ʺ

,

 

The

 

New

 

Republic

 

2

 

June

 

1997:22.

 

———

 

(2002),

 

Life,

 

liberty,

 

and

 

the

 

defense

 

of

 

dignity:

 

the

 

challenge

 

for

 

bioethics

.

 

1st

 

ed.

 

San

 

Francisco:

 

Encounter

 

Books.

 

Kurzweil,

 

R.

 

(1999),

 

The

 

Age

 

of

 

Spiritual

 

Machines:

 

When

 

computers

 

exceed

 

human

 

intelligence

.

 

New

 

York:

 

Viking.

 

La

 

Mettrie,

 

J.

 

O.

 

d.

 

(1996),

 

Machine

 

man

 

and

 

other

 

writings

,

 

Cambridge

 

texts

 

in

 

the

 

history

 

of

 

philosophy

.

 

Cambridge:

 

Cambridge

 

University

 

Press.

 

Leslie,

 

J.

 

(1996),

 

The

 

End

 

of

 

the

 

World:

 

The

 

Science

 

and

 

Ethics

 

of

 

Human

 

Extinction

.

 

London:

 

Routledge.

 

Minsky,

 

M.

 

(1994),

 ʺ

Will

 

Robots

 

Inherit

 

the

 

Earth?

ʺ 

Scientific

 

American

.

 

Mitchell,

 

S.

 

(2004),

 

Gilgamesh:

 

a

 

new

 

English

 

version

.

 

New

 

York:

 

Free

 

Press.

 

Moore,

 

G.

 

E.

 

(1965),

 ʺ

Cramming

 

more

 

components

 

onto

 

integrated

 

circuits

ʺ

,

 

Electronics

 

38

 

(8).

 

Moravec,

 

H.

 

(1989),

 

Mind

 

Children

.

 

Harvard:

 

Harvard

 

University

 

Press.

 

———

 

(1999),

 

Robot:

 

Mere

 

Machine

 

to

 

Transcendent

 

Mind

.

 

New

 

York:

 

Oxford

 

University

 

Press.

 

More,

 

M.

 

Principles

 

of

 

Extropy,

 

Version

 

3.11

 

2003.

 

http://www.extropy.org/principles.htm

.

 

Newman,

 

W.

 

R.

 

(2004),

 

Promethean

 

ambitions:

 

alchemy

 

and

 

the

 

quest

 

to

 

perfect

 

nature

.

 

Chicago:

 

University

 

of

 

Chicago

 

Press.

 

Nietzsche,

 

F.

 

W.

 

(1908),

 

Also

 

sprach

 

Zarathustra:

 

ein

 

Buch

 

fèur

 

alle

 

und

 

keinen

.

 

Leipzig:

 

Insel

â€

Verlag.

 

Office,

 

U.

 

S.

 

G.

 

P.

 

(1949),

 ʺ

Trials

 

of

 

War

 

Criminals

 

before

 

the

 

Nuremberg

 

Military

 

Tribunals

 

under

 

Control

 

Council

 

Law

 

No.

 

10

ʺ

,

 

2:181

â€

182.

 

Orwell,

 

G.

 

(1949),

 

Nineteen

 

eighty

â€

four,

 

a

 

novel

.

 

New

 

York:

 

Harcourt.

 

Parens,

 

E.

 

(1998),

 

Enhancing

 

human

 

traits:

 

ethical

 

and

 

social

 

implications

,

 

Hastings

 

Center

 

studies

 

in

 

ethics

.

 

Washington,

 

D.C.:

 

Georgetown

 

University

 

Press.

 

Parfit,

 

D.

 

(1984),

 

Reasons

 

and

 

Persons

.

 

Oxford:

 

Clarendon

 

Press.

 

Pearce,

 

D.

 

The

 

Hedonistic

 

Imperative

 

2004.

 

http://www.hedweb.com/hedab.htm

.

 

Pence,

 

G.

 

E.

 

(1998),

 

Who

ʹ

s

 

afraid

 

of

 

human

 

cloning?

 

Lanham:

 

Rowman

 

&

 

Littlefield.

 

Pico

 

della

 

Mirandola,

 

G.

 

(1956),

 

Oration

 

on

 

the

 

dignity

 

of

 

man

.

 

Chicago:

 

Gateway

 

Editions.

 

Posner,

 

R.

 

(2004),

 

Catastrophe

.

 

Oxford:

 

Oxford

 

University

 

Press.

 

Rees,

 

M.

 

(2003),

 

Our

 

Final

 

Hour:

 

A

 

Scientist

ʹ

s

 

Warning:

 

How

 

Terror,

 

Error,

 

and

 

Environmental

 

Disaster

 

Threaten

 

Humankind

ʹ

s

 

Future

 

in

 

This

 

Century

 â€Â 

On

 

Earth

 

and

 

Beyond

:

 

Basic

 

Books.

 

 

29

background image

 

30

Regis,

 

E.

 

(1990),

 

Great

 

mambo

 

chicken

 

and

 

the

 

transhuman

 

condition:

 

science

 

slightly

 

over

 

the

 

edge

.

 

Reading,

 

Mass.:

 

Addison

â€

Wesley.

 

———

 

(1994),

 ʺ

Meet

 

the

 

Extropians

ʺ

,

 

Wired

 

2

 

(10).

 

Russell,

 

B.

 

(1924),

 

Icarus;

 

or

 

The

 

future

 

of

 

science

.

 

London:

 

K.

 

Paul,

 

Trench,

 

Trubner

 

&

 

Co.,

 

ltd.

 

Savulescu,

 

J.

 

(2001),

 ʺ

Procreative

 

Beneficence:

 

Why

 

We

 

Should

 

Select

 

the

 

Best

 

Children

ʺ

,

 

Bioethics

 

15

 

(5

â€

6):413

â€

426.

 

Shelley,

 

M.

 

W.

 

(1818),

 

Frankenstein;

 

or,

 

The

 

modern

 

Prometheus

.

 

London,:

 

Printed

 

for

 

Lackington,

 

Hughes,

 

Harding,

 

Mavor,

 

&

 

Jones.

 

Singer,

 

P.

 

(2003),

 ʺ

Shopping

 

at

 

the

 

Genetic

 

Supermarket

ʺ

,

 

in

 

SY

 

Song,

 

YM

 

Koo

 

and

 

DRJ.

 

Macer

 

(eds.),

 

Bioethics

 

in

 

Asia

 

in

 

the

 

21st

 

Century

:

 

Eubios

 

Ethics

 

Institute,

 

143

â€

156.

 

Stock,

 

G.

 

(2002),

 

Redesigning

 

Humans:

 

Our

 

Inevitable

 

Genetic

 

Future

:

 

Houghton

 

Mifflin

 

Company.

 

Teilhard

 

de

 

Chardin,

 

P.

 

(1964),

 

The

 

future

 

of

 

man

.

 

New

 

York:

 

Harper

 

&

 

Row.

 

Tipler,

 

F.

 

(1994),

 

The

 

Physics

 

of

 

Immortality

.

 

New

 

York:

 

Doubleday.

 

Turing,

 

A.

 

(1950),

 ʺ

Computing

 

machinery

 

and

 

intelligence

ʺ

,

 

Mind

 

59:433

â€

460.

 

Ulam,

 

S.

 

(1958),

 ʺ

John

 

von

 

Neumann

 

1903

â€

1957

ʺ

,

 

Bulletin

 

of

 

the

 

American

 

Mathematical

 

Society

 

(May).

 

Vinge,

 

V.

 

(1993),

 ʺ

The

 

Coming

 

Technological

 

Singularity

ʺ

,

 

Whole

 

Earth

 

Review

 

Winter

 

issue.

 

Vita

â€

More,

 

N.

 

Transhumanist

 

Arts

 

Statement

 

2002.

 

http://www.transhumanist.biz/transart.htm

.

 

Walker,

 

M.

 

(2002),

 ʺ

Prolegomena

 

to

 

Any

 

Future

 

Philosophy

ʺ

,

 

Journal

 

of

 

Evolution

 

and

 

Technology

 

10.

 

World_Medical_Organization

 

(1996),

 ʺ

Declaration

 

of

 

Helsinki

ʺ

,

 

British

 

Medical

 

Journal

 

313

 

(7070):1448

â€

1449.

 

WTA

 

The

 

Transhumanist

 

Declaration

 

2002.

 

http://transhumanism.org/index.php/WTA/declaration/

.

 

Yudkowsky,

 

E.

 

Collective

 

Volition

 

2004.

 

http://www.singinst.org/friendly/collective

â€

volition.html

.

 

 


Document Outline